T-symmetry: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>Stevertigo
mNo edit summary
 
en>Dude1818
Repairing links to disambiguation pages - You can help!
Line 1: Line 1:
Almost everyone is now aware that life-style illnesses are a leading killer inside today's planet and today the query on most women's notice is: are there diets which function for women? If you find yourself asking this question then we are not alone inside the quest for diets which work quick for women.<br><br>[http://safedietsthatwork.beep.com/ diet plans] really have the above stated criteria and let the dieter to consume what they want at certain specific periods. This would ensure which the dieter does not get into binge eating and does not drop away within the diet.<br><br>For efficient dieting it's important which we have such healthy food at standard interval which is 4 instances or 4 meals inside a day. A suggestion is the fact that you must avoid coffee. Instead we can sip on green tea. Effective diet plans for weigh reduction equally involves drinking of more water. You should take eight glasses per day and this is efficient in eliminating the toxins of body. Water also assists inside filling fuller for belly. It said if you drink warm water each morning you'll be able to get rid of fat and also it assists is eliminating the bloating.<br><br>Remember when you start your search for a diet plan or diet supplement to slim faster is to choose a plan which ensures you're nevertheless receiving the vitamins, vitamins, and minerals you body demands to stay healthy. The best plus simplest method to slim quicker is by reducing your calorie intake plus exercising to grow your metabolism. This way you can choose how swiftly we want to lose weight. Stay away from fattening foods, nevertheless eat 3 balanced food a day.<br><br>As difficult as it is to believe diets are nothing else that the way we eat! So id you'll McDonnald every day, you're possibly on McBurger diet. If you go to your closest Pizza store, you may be on a pizza diet. Those are not diets that will help you to get rid of fat plus reveal your six-pack. I promise we that.<br><br>There are numerous different kinds of diet programs. The first is the fixed-menu program in that they usually provide we the list of the foods to eat. This is fairly easy to follow but, there is usually a limited selection of foods that you can choose, and thus there are bored by them. Nevertheless, if you are creative or utilizing such a common meal plan, you are able to find many dishes online which may suit a taste.<br><br>As you are able to see, these five healthy eating details for kids usually create it much simpler for you to receive started making sure the own child is eating healthy for a better future.
{{About||causality in philosophy|Causality|the disambiguation page on causality|Causation (disambiguation){{!}}Causation}}
{{multiple issues|
{{Refimprove|date=July 2008}}
{{Cleanup|date=December 2008}}
}}
 
'''Causality''' is the relationship between [[cause]]s and effects.<ref>Green, Celia (2003). ''The Lost Cause: Causation and the Mind–Body Problem''. Oxford: Oxford Forum. ISBN 0-9536772-1-4. Includes three chapters on causality at the microlevel in physics.</ref><ref>Bunge, Mario (1959). ''Causality: the place of the causal principle in modern science''. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.</ref>  It is considered to be fundamental to all natural [[science]], especially [[physics]]. [[Causality]] is also a topic studied from the perspectives of [[philosophy]] and [[statistics]].
 
== Cause and effect in physics ==
 
In physics it is useful to interpret certain terms of a physical theory as causes and other terms as effects. Thus, in [[Newton's laws of motion|classical (Newtonian) mechanics]] a cause may be represented by a [[force]] acting on a body, and an effect by the acceleration which follows as quantitatively explained by [[Force#Newton's second law|Newton's second law]]. For different physical theories the notions of cause and effect may be different. For instance, in [[General relativity#Geometry of Newtonian gravity|the general theory of relativity]], acceleration is not an effect (since it is not a generally relativistic [[Tensor|vector]]); the general relativistic effects comparable to those of Newtonian mechanics are the deviations from [[geodesic (general relativity)|geodesic motion]] in curved [[spacetime]].<ref>e.g. R. Adler, M. Bazin, M. Schiffer, ''Introduction to general relativity'', McGraw–Hill Book Company, 1965, section 2.3.</ref> Also, the meaning of "uncaused motion" is dependent on the theory being employed: for Newton it is [[Newton's first law|inertial motion]] (constant velocity with respect to an [[inertial frame of reference]]), in the general theory of relativity it is geodesic motion (to be compared with frictionless motion on the surface of a sphere at constant tangential velocity along a [[great circle]]). So what constitutes a "cause" and what constitutes an "effect" depends on the total system of explanation in which the putative causal sequence is embedded.
 
A formulation of physical laws in terms of cause and effect is useful for the purposes of [[explanation]] and [[prediction]]. For instance, in Newtonian mechanics, an observed acceleration can be explained by reference to an applied force. So [[Force#Newtonian mechanics|Newton's second law]] can be used to predict the force necessary to realize a desired acceleration.
 
In classical physics, a cause should always ''precede'' its effect. In relativity theory the equivalent restriction limits causes to the back (past) [[light cone]] of the event to be explained (the "effect"), and any effect of a cause must lie in the cause's front (future) light cone. These restrictions are consistent with the grounded belief (or assumption) that causal influences cannot travel faster than the speed of light and/or backwards in time.
 
Another requirement, at least valid at the level of human experience, is that cause and effect be mediated across space and time (requirement of ''contiguity''). This requirement has been very influential in the past, in the first place as a result of direct observation of causal processes (like pushing a cart), in the second place as a problematic aspect of Newton's theory of gravitation (attraction of the earth by the sun by means of [[Action at a distance (physics)|action at a distance]]) replacing mechanistic proposals like [[The World (Descartes)#Descartes' Universe|Descartes' vortex theory]]; in the third place as an incentive to develop dynamic [[Classical field theory|field theories]] (e.g., [[Electromagnetism#Classical electrodynamics|Maxwell's electrodynamics]] and [[Einstein field equations|Einstein's general theory of relativity]]) restoring contiguity in the transmission of influences in a more successful way than did Descartes' theory.
 
The empiricists' aversion to metaphysical explanations (like Descartes' vortex theory) lends heavy influence against the idea of the importance of causality. Causality has accordingly sometimes been downplayed (e.g., Newton's "[[Hypotheses non fingo]]"). According to [[Ernst Mach]]<ref>Ernst Mach, ''Die Mechanik in ihrer Entwicklung, Historisch-kritisch dargestellt'', Akademie-Verlag, Berlin, 1988, section 2.7.</ref> the notion of force in Newton's second law was [[Pleonasm|pleonastic]], tautological and superfluous. Indeed it is possible to consider the Newtonian equations of motion of the gravitational interaction of two bodies,
 
:<math> m_1 \frac{d^2 {\mathbf r}_1 }{ dt^2} = -\frac{m_1 m_2 g ({\mathbf r}_1 - {\mathbf r}_2)}{ |{\mathbf r}_1 - {\mathbf r}_2|^3};\; m_2 \frac{d^2 {\mathbf r}_2 }{dt^2} = -\frac{m_1 m_2 g ({\mathbf r}_2 - {\mathbf r}_1) }{ |{\mathbf r}_2 - {\mathbf r}_1|^3}, </math>
 
as two coupled equations describing the positions <math> \scriptstyle {\mathbf r}_1(t) </math> and <math> \scriptstyle {\mathbf r}_2(t) </math> of the two bodies, ''without interpreting the right hand sides of these equations as forces''; the equations just describe a process of interaction, without any necessity to interpret one body as the cause of the motion of the other, and allow one to predict the states of the system at later (as well as earlier) times.
 
The ordinary situations in which humans singled out some factors in a physical interaction as being prior and therefore supplying the "because" of the interaction were often ones in which humans decided to bring about some state of affairs and directed their energies to producing that state of affairs—a process that took time to establish and left a new state of affairs that persisted beyond the time of activity of the actor. It would be difficult and pointless, however, to explain the motions of binary stars with respect to each other in that way.
 
The possibility of such a time-independent view is at the basis of the [[deductive-nomological]] (D-N) view of scientific explanation, considering an event to be explained if it can be subsumed under a scientific law. In the D-N view, a physical state is considered to be explained if, applying the (deterministic) law, it can be derived from given initial conditions. (Such initial conditions could include the momenta and distance from each other of binary stars at any given moment.) Such 'explanation by determinism' is sometimes referred to as [[Determinism#Varieties|causal determinism]]. A disadvantage of the D-N view is that causality and determinism are more or less identified. Thus, in [[classical physics]], it was assumed that all events are caused by earlier ones according to the known laws of nature, culminating in [[Pierre-Simon Laplace]]'s claim that if the current state of the world were known with precision, it could be computed for any time in the future or the past (see [[Laplace's demon]]). However, this is usually referred to as Laplace ''determinism'' (rather than `Laplace causality') because it hinges on [[Determinism#In mathematical models|determinism in mathematical models]] as dealt with in the mathematical [[Cauchy problem]]. Confusion of causality and determinism is particularly acute in [[quantum mechanics]], this theory being acausal in the sense that it is unable in many cases to identify the causes of actually observed effects or to predict the effects of identical causes, but arguably [[Quantum mechanics#Theory|deterministic]] in some interpretations (e.g. if the wave function is presumed not to actually collapse as in the [[many-worlds interpretation]], or if its collapse is due to [[hidden variable theory|hidden variables]], or simply redefining determinism as meaning that probabilities rather than specific effects are determined).
 
In [[modern physics]], the notion of causality had to be clarified. The insights of the theory of [[special relativity]] confirmed the assumption of causality, but they made the meaning of the word "simultaneous" observer-dependent.<ref>A. Einstein, "Zur Elektrodynamik bewegter Koerper", ''Annalen der Physik'' '''17''', 891–921 (1905).</ref> Consequently, the relativistic principle of causality says that the cause must precede its effect ''according to all [[inertial]] observers''. This is equivalent to the statement that the cause and its effect are separated by a [[timelike]] interval, and the effect belongs to the future of its cause. If a timelike interval separates the two events, this means that a signal could be sent between them at less than the speed of light. On the other hand, if signals could move faster than the speed of light, this would violate causality because it would allow a signal to be sent across [[spacelike]] intervals, which means that at least to some inertial observers the signal would travel ''backward in time''. For this reason, special relativity does not allow communication faster than the [[speed of light]].
 
In the theory of [[general relativity]], the concept of causality is generalized in the most straightforward way: the effect must belong to the future light cone of its cause, even if the [[spacetime]] is curved. New subtleties must be taken into account when we investigate causality in [[quantum mechanics]] and relativistic [[quantum field theory]] in particular. In quantum field theory, causality is closely related to the [[principle of locality]]. However, the principle of locality is disputed: whether it strictly holds depends on the [[interpretation of quantum mechanics]] chosen, especially for experiments involving [[quantum entanglement]] that satisfy [[Bell's Theorem]].
 
Despite these subtleties, causality remains an important and valid concept in physical theories. For example, the notion that events can be ordered into causes and effects is necessary to prevent (or at least outline) [[causality paradox]]es such as the [[grandfather paradox]], which asks what happens if a time-traveler kills his own grandfather before he ever meets the time-traveler's grandmother.  See also [[Chronology protection conjecture]].
 
===Distributed causality===
 
Theories in [[physics]] like the [[Butterfly effect]] from [[chaos theory]] open up the possibility of a type of [[distributed parameter systems]] in causality. The butterfly effect theory proposes:
<blockquote>"Small variations of the initial condition of a nonlinear dynamical system may produce large variations in the long term behavior of the system."</blockquote> This opens up the opportunity to understand a distributed causality.
 
A related way to interpret the [[Butterfly effect]] is to see it as highlighting the difference between the application of the notion of causality in physics and a [[Causality|more general use of causality]] as represented by [[INUS|Mackie's INUS conditions]]. In physics, in general, only those conditions are (explicitly) taken into account, that are both necessary and sufficient. For instance, when a massive sphere is caused to roll down a slope starting from a point of [[Mechanical equilibrium|unstable equilibrium]], then its velocity is assumed to be caused by the force of gravity accelerating it; the small push that was needed to set it into motion is not explicitly dealt with as a cause. In order to be a physical cause there must be a certain proportionality with the ensuing effect. A distinction is drawn between triggering and causation of the ball's motion. By the same token the butterfly can be seen as triggering a tornado, its cause being assumed to be seated in the atmospherical energies already present beforehand, rather than in the movements of a butterfly.
 
===Causal dynamical triangulation===
{{main|Causal dynamical triangulation}}
'''Causal dynamical triangulation''' (abbreviated as "CDT") invented by [[Renate Loll]], [[Jan Ambjorn|Jan Ambjørn]] and [[Jerzy Jurkiewicz]], and popularized by [[Fotini Markopoulou]] and [[Lee Smolin]], is an approach to [[quantum gravity]] that like [[loop quantum gravity]] is [[background independent]].  This means that it does not assume any pre-existing arena (dimensional space), but rather attempts to show how the [[spacetime]] fabric itself evolves.  The [http://loops05.aei.mpg.de/ Loops '05] conference, hosted by many loop quantum gravity theorists, included several presentations which discussed CDT in great depth, and revealed it to be a pivotal insight for theorists.  It has sparked considerable interest as it appears to have a good semi-classical description.  At large scales, it re-creates the familiar 4-dimensional spacetime, but it shows spacetime to be 2-d near the [[Planck scale]], and reveals a [[fractal]] structure on slices of constant time. Using a structure called a [[simplex]], it divides spacetime into tiny triangular sections.  A simplex is the generalized form of a [[triangle]], in various dimensions.  A 3-simplex is usually called a [[tetrahedron]], and the 4-simplex, which is the basic building block in this theory, is also known as the pentatope, or [[pentachoron]].  Each simplex is geometrically flat, but simplices can be "glued" together in a variety of ways to create curved spacetimes.  Where previous attempts at triangulation of quantum spaces have produced jumbled universes with far too many dimensions, or minimal universes with too few, CDT avoids this problem by allowing only those configurations where cause precedes any event.  In other words, the timelines of all joined edges of simplices must agree.
 
Thus, maybe, causality lies in the foundation of the [[spacetime]] geometry.
 
===Causal sets===
{{main|Causal sets}}
In causal set theory causality takes an even more prominent place. The basis for this approach to quantum gravity is in a theorem by [[David Malament]]. This theorem states that the [[causal structure]] of a spacetime suffices to reconstruct its conformal class. So knowing the conformal factor and the causal structure is enough to know the spacetime. Based on this  [[Rafael Sorkin]] proposed the idea of Causal Set Theory.
Causal Set Theory is a fundamentally discrete approach to quantum gravity. The causal structure of the spacetime is represented as a [[Poset]], while the conformal factor can be reconstructed by identifying each poset element with a unit volume.
 
== See also ==
* [[Causal contact]]
* [[Causal system]]
* [[Particle horizon]]
* [[Philosophy of physics]]
* [[Retrocausality]]
* [[Synchronicity]]
* [[Wheeler–Feynman absorber theory|Wheeler–Feynman time-symmetric theory for electrodynamics]]
 
==References==
{{reflist}}
 
==Further reading==
*Bohm, David. (2005). ''Causality and Chance in Modern Physics''. London:  Taylor and Francis.
 
==External links==
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/causation-process/ Causal Processes, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
* [http://www.black-holes.org/relativity3.html Caltech Tutorial on Relativity] &mdash; A nice discussion of how observers moving relatively to each other see different slices of time.
* [http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/0107091 Faster-than-c signals, special relativity, and causality]. This article explains that faster than light signals do not necessarily lead to a violation of causality.
* by John G. Cramer:
**[http://www.analogsf.com/0612/altview.shtml EPR Communication: Signals from the Future?] "In this column I want to tell you about this causality-violating communications scheme and its possible consequences."
**[http://mist.npl.washington.edu/npl/int_rep/tiqm/TI_toc.html The Transactional Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics] "3.10 The Arrow of Time in the Transactional Interpretation – The formalism of quantum mechanics, at least in its relativistically invariant formulation, is completely even handed in dealing with the "arrow" of time, the distinction between future and past time directions."
 
{{DEFAULTSORT:Causality (Physics)}}
[[Category:Causality]]
[[Category:Concepts in physics]]
[[Category:Philosophy of physics]]
[[Category:Time travel]]
 
[[ko:인과율]]
[[it:Sistema causale]]
[[ja:因果律]]

Revision as of 04:13, 19 November 2013

29 yr old Orthopaedic Surgeon Grippo from Saint-Paul, spends time with interests including model railways, top property developers in singapore developers in singapore and dolls. Finished a cruise ship experience that included passing by Runic Stones and Church. Template:Multiple issues

Causality is the relationship between causes and effects.[1][2] It is considered to be fundamental to all natural science, especially physics. Causality is also a topic studied from the perspectives of philosophy and statistics.

Cause and effect in physics

In physics it is useful to interpret certain terms of a physical theory as causes and other terms as effects. Thus, in classical (Newtonian) mechanics a cause may be represented by a force acting on a body, and an effect by the acceleration which follows as quantitatively explained by Newton's second law. For different physical theories the notions of cause and effect may be different. For instance, in the general theory of relativity, acceleration is not an effect (since it is not a generally relativistic vector); the general relativistic effects comparable to those of Newtonian mechanics are the deviations from geodesic motion in curved spacetime.[3] Also, the meaning of "uncaused motion" is dependent on the theory being employed: for Newton it is inertial motion (constant velocity with respect to an inertial frame of reference), in the general theory of relativity it is geodesic motion (to be compared with frictionless motion on the surface of a sphere at constant tangential velocity along a great circle). So what constitutes a "cause" and what constitutes an "effect" depends on the total system of explanation in which the putative causal sequence is embedded.

A formulation of physical laws in terms of cause and effect is useful for the purposes of explanation and prediction. For instance, in Newtonian mechanics, an observed acceleration can be explained by reference to an applied force. So Newton's second law can be used to predict the force necessary to realize a desired acceleration.

In classical physics, a cause should always precede its effect. In relativity theory the equivalent restriction limits causes to the back (past) light cone of the event to be explained (the "effect"), and any effect of a cause must lie in the cause's front (future) light cone. These restrictions are consistent with the grounded belief (or assumption) that causal influences cannot travel faster than the speed of light and/or backwards in time.

Another requirement, at least valid at the level of human experience, is that cause and effect be mediated across space and time (requirement of contiguity). This requirement has been very influential in the past, in the first place as a result of direct observation of causal processes (like pushing a cart), in the second place as a problematic aspect of Newton's theory of gravitation (attraction of the earth by the sun by means of action at a distance) replacing mechanistic proposals like Descartes' vortex theory; in the third place as an incentive to develop dynamic field theories (e.g., Maxwell's electrodynamics and Einstein's general theory of relativity) restoring contiguity in the transmission of influences in a more successful way than did Descartes' theory.

The empiricists' aversion to metaphysical explanations (like Descartes' vortex theory) lends heavy influence against the idea of the importance of causality. Causality has accordingly sometimes been downplayed (e.g., Newton's "Hypotheses non fingo"). According to Ernst Mach[4] the notion of force in Newton's second law was pleonastic, tautological and superfluous. Indeed it is possible to consider the Newtonian equations of motion of the gravitational interaction of two bodies,

as two coupled equations describing the positions and of the two bodies, without interpreting the right hand sides of these equations as forces; the equations just describe a process of interaction, without any necessity to interpret one body as the cause of the motion of the other, and allow one to predict the states of the system at later (as well as earlier) times.

The ordinary situations in which humans singled out some factors in a physical interaction as being prior and therefore supplying the "because" of the interaction were often ones in which humans decided to bring about some state of affairs and directed their energies to producing that state of affairs—a process that took time to establish and left a new state of affairs that persisted beyond the time of activity of the actor. It would be difficult and pointless, however, to explain the motions of binary stars with respect to each other in that way.

The possibility of such a time-independent view is at the basis of the deductive-nomological (D-N) view of scientific explanation, considering an event to be explained if it can be subsumed under a scientific law. In the D-N view, a physical state is considered to be explained if, applying the (deterministic) law, it can be derived from given initial conditions. (Such initial conditions could include the momenta and distance from each other of binary stars at any given moment.) Such 'explanation by determinism' is sometimes referred to as causal determinism. A disadvantage of the D-N view is that causality and determinism are more or less identified. Thus, in classical physics, it was assumed that all events are caused by earlier ones according to the known laws of nature, culminating in Pierre-Simon Laplace's claim that if the current state of the world were known with precision, it could be computed for any time in the future or the past (see Laplace's demon). However, this is usually referred to as Laplace determinism (rather than `Laplace causality') because it hinges on determinism in mathematical models as dealt with in the mathematical Cauchy problem. Confusion of causality and determinism is particularly acute in quantum mechanics, this theory being acausal in the sense that it is unable in many cases to identify the causes of actually observed effects or to predict the effects of identical causes, but arguably deterministic in some interpretations (e.g. if the wave function is presumed not to actually collapse as in the many-worlds interpretation, or if its collapse is due to hidden variables, or simply redefining determinism as meaning that probabilities rather than specific effects are determined).

In modern physics, the notion of causality had to be clarified. The insights of the theory of special relativity confirmed the assumption of causality, but they made the meaning of the word "simultaneous" observer-dependent.[5] Consequently, the relativistic principle of causality says that the cause must precede its effect according to all inertial observers. This is equivalent to the statement that the cause and its effect are separated by a timelike interval, and the effect belongs to the future of its cause. If a timelike interval separates the two events, this means that a signal could be sent between them at less than the speed of light. On the other hand, if signals could move faster than the speed of light, this would violate causality because it would allow a signal to be sent across spacelike intervals, which means that at least to some inertial observers the signal would travel backward in time. For this reason, special relativity does not allow communication faster than the speed of light.

In the theory of general relativity, the concept of causality is generalized in the most straightforward way: the effect must belong to the future light cone of its cause, even if the spacetime is curved. New subtleties must be taken into account when we investigate causality in quantum mechanics and relativistic quantum field theory in particular. In quantum field theory, causality is closely related to the principle of locality. However, the principle of locality is disputed: whether it strictly holds depends on the interpretation of quantum mechanics chosen, especially for experiments involving quantum entanglement that satisfy Bell's Theorem.

Despite these subtleties, causality remains an important and valid concept in physical theories. For example, the notion that events can be ordered into causes and effects is necessary to prevent (or at least outline) causality paradoxes such as the grandfather paradox, which asks what happens if a time-traveler kills his own grandfather before he ever meets the time-traveler's grandmother. See also Chronology protection conjecture.

Distributed causality

Theories in physics like the Butterfly effect from chaos theory open up the possibility of a type of distributed parameter systems in causality. The butterfly effect theory proposes:

"Small variations of the initial condition of a nonlinear dynamical system may produce large variations in the long term behavior of the system."

This opens up the opportunity to understand a distributed causality.

A related way to interpret the Butterfly effect is to see it as highlighting the difference between the application of the notion of causality in physics and a more general use of causality as represented by Mackie's INUS conditions. In physics, in general, only those conditions are (explicitly) taken into account, that are both necessary and sufficient. For instance, when a massive sphere is caused to roll down a slope starting from a point of unstable equilibrium, then its velocity is assumed to be caused by the force of gravity accelerating it; the small push that was needed to set it into motion is not explicitly dealt with as a cause. In order to be a physical cause there must be a certain proportionality with the ensuing effect. A distinction is drawn between triggering and causation of the ball's motion. By the same token the butterfly can be seen as triggering a tornado, its cause being assumed to be seated in the atmospherical energies already present beforehand, rather than in the movements of a butterfly.

Causal dynamical triangulation

Mining Engineer (Excluding Oil ) Truman from Alma, loves to spend time knotting, largest property developers in singapore developers in singapore and stamp collecting. Recently had a family visit to Urnes Stave Church. Causal dynamical triangulation (abbreviated as "CDT") invented by Renate Loll, Jan Ambjørn and Jerzy Jurkiewicz, and popularized by Fotini Markopoulou and Lee Smolin, is an approach to quantum gravity that like loop quantum gravity is background independent. This means that it does not assume any pre-existing arena (dimensional space), but rather attempts to show how the spacetime fabric itself evolves. The Loops '05 conference, hosted by many loop quantum gravity theorists, included several presentations which discussed CDT in great depth, and revealed it to be a pivotal insight for theorists. It has sparked considerable interest as it appears to have a good semi-classical description. At large scales, it re-creates the familiar 4-dimensional spacetime, but it shows spacetime to be 2-d near the Planck scale, and reveals a fractal structure on slices of constant time. Using a structure called a simplex, it divides spacetime into tiny triangular sections. A simplex is the generalized form of a triangle, in various dimensions. A 3-simplex is usually called a tetrahedron, and the 4-simplex, which is the basic building block in this theory, is also known as the pentatope, or pentachoron. Each simplex is geometrically flat, but simplices can be "glued" together in a variety of ways to create curved spacetimes. Where previous attempts at triangulation of quantum spaces have produced jumbled universes with far too many dimensions, or minimal universes with too few, CDT avoids this problem by allowing only those configurations where cause precedes any event. In other words, the timelines of all joined edges of simplices must agree.

Thus, maybe, causality lies in the foundation of the spacetime geometry.

Causal sets

Mining Engineer (Excluding Oil ) Truman from Alma, loves to spend time knotting, largest property developers in singapore developers in singapore and stamp collecting. Recently had a family visit to Urnes Stave Church. In causal set theory causality takes an even more prominent place. The basis for this approach to quantum gravity is in a theorem by David Malament. This theorem states that the causal structure of a spacetime suffices to reconstruct its conformal class. So knowing the conformal factor and the causal structure is enough to know the spacetime. Based on this Rafael Sorkin proposed the idea of Causal Set Theory. Causal Set Theory is a fundamentally discrete approach to quantum gravity. The causal structure of the spacetime is represented as a Poset, while the conformal factor can be reconstructed by identifying each poset element with a unit volume.

See also

References

43 year old Petroleum Engineer Harry from Deep River, usually spends time with hobbies and interests like renting movies, property developers in singapore new condominium and vehicle racing. Constantly enjoys going to destinations like Camino Real de Tierra Adentro.

Further reading

  • Bohm, David. (2005). Causality and Chance in Modern Physics. London: Taylor and Francis.

External links

ko:인과율 it:Sistema causale ja:因果律

  1. Green, Celia (2003). The Lost Cause: Causation and the Mind–Body Problem. Oxford: Oxford Forum. ISBN 0-9536772-1-4. Includes three chapters on causality at the microlevel in physics.
  2. Bunge, Mario (1959). Causality: the place of the causal principle in modern science. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  3. e.g. R. Adler, M. Bazin, M. Schiffer, Introduction to general relativity, McGraw–Hill Book Company, 1965, section 2.3.
  4. Ernst Mach, Die Mechanik in ihrer Entwicklung, Historisch-kritisch dargestellt, Akademie-Verlag, Berlin, 1988, section 2.7.
  5. A. Einstein, "Zur Elektrodynamik bewegter Koerper", Annalen der Physik 17, 891–921 (1905).