Riesz representation theorem: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>Policron
mNo edit summary
 
Line 1: Line 1:
Nokia  [http://www.rottentomatoes.com/user/1083060/blogs/?id=793517 pc suite free download] introduced the X3, an affordable new feature phone debuting as part of Nokia's new associated with X Series devices. The Nokia X3 is one of the highest mobile phones for personal, socializing, or even just business uses. Them.2" QVGA display of the Nokia X3 with active matrix technology consists of a resolution of 320 x 240 pixels and shows upwards of 262,144 colors.<br><br>Sony Xperia S is powered by a Qualcomm MSM8260 Snapdragon dual-core 1.5 GHz processor and Adreno 220 GPU. On a memory front, it offers 1 GB of RAM and 32 GB of internal shed. Sadly, it doesn't possess a microSD card slot so you will wind up limited towards the internal reminiscence.<br><br>From info it seem that an extremely some problems in your mobile's software. It may get corrupted or get damaged and that is why you are becoming such involving problem. For example , you always be upgrade your mobile's software to fix this difficulty.<br><br> <br><br>With its brilliant red color, in order to sure help make heads twist. No doubt, this is a show stealer. Its stylish looks conceal the actuality that it is really a simple budget phone.<br><br>The perhaps most obviously feature in Lava B8 phone is that it has Wireless LAN connectivity (Wi-Fi). Lava B8 does not boast3G it support. Moreover the phone has remarkable 3.2 Mega pixels photo snapper to click images fit quality and true lighting. It has integrated without the pain . cool video and audio features. It supports the multi music formats pertaining to example MP3 / WMA / eAAC+, stereo FM radio with RDS, FM transmitter, 3.5mm audio jack, other folks. It is well featured mobile at affordable quote. The Lava b8 charges are Rs.3, 999.<br><br>The camera lens is placed on the back, protected by a covering. To activate the camera simply slide the talk about. The screen automatically adjusts a few landscape mode and acts like a viewfinder. By using a camera capture key and zoom keys, Nokia N73 looks that can compare with a camcorder. Though the phone lacks any self portrait mirror, it offers a superior something far better - an extra camera located just across the screen in upper right-hand corner. Nokia packages the Nokia N73 with most elementary accessories. Consists of an AC adapter, USB cable, a stereo headset, a wrist strap, a wipe cloth, Nokia pc suite software and reference tutorial.<br><br>Memory- Trucking jobs internal memory of 30 MB which were expanded to 2 GB any microSD greetings card. The phonebook also has a capacity to help keep up to 1000 other details. You will never exhausted storage space here.<br><br>The multimedia of cell phone is a first-rate hub for videos and audio music. The Integrated music player supports MP3/MP4/AAC/eAAC+/WMA audio file formats along with the the video player can perform playing They would.263 & MPEG4 file. Besides these gaming, good battery back up and stylish looks make this phone the best choice.
{{lowercase|title=μ-recursive function}}
In [[mathematical logic]] and [[computer science]], the '''μ-recursive functions''' are a class of [[partial function]]s from [[natural number]]s to [[natural number]]s which are "computable" in an intuitive sense. In fact, in [[Computability theory (computation)|computability theory]] it is shown that the μ-recursive functions are precisely the functions that can be computed by [[Turing machine]]s. The μ-recursive functions are closely related to [[primitive recursive function]]s, and their inductive definition (below) builds upon that of the primitive recursive functions. However, not every μ-recursive function is a primitive recursive function&mdash;the most famous example is the [[Ackermann function]].
 
Other equivalent classes of functions are the [[lambda-recursive function|&lambda;-recursive functions]] and the functions that can be computed by [[Markov algorithm]]s.
 
The set of all recursive functions is known as [[R (complexity)|R]] in [[computational complexity theory]].
 
==Definition==
 
The '''μ-recursive functions''' (or '''partial μ-recursive functions''') are partial functions that take finite tuples of natural numbers and return a single natural number.  They are the smallest class of partial functions that includes the initial functions and is closed under composition, primitive recursion, and the [[μ operator]].
 
The smallest class of functions including the initial functions and closed under composition and primitive recursion (i.e. without minimisation) is the class of [[primitive recursive functions]].  While all primitive recursive functions are total, this is not true of partial recursive functions; for example, the minimisation of the successor function is undefined. The primitive recursive functions are a subset of the total recursive functions, which are a subset of the partial recursive functions. For example, the [[Ackermann function]] can be proven to be total recursive, but not primitive.
 
Initial or "basic" functions: (In the following the subscripting is per Kleene (1952) p.&nbsp;219. For more about some of the various symbolisms found in the literature see [[#Symbolism|Symbolism]] below.)
 
#'''Constant function''': For each natural number <math>n\,</math> and every <math>k\,</math>:
#:<math>f(x_1,\ldots,x_k) = n\,</math>.
#:Alternative definitions use compositions of the successor function and use a '''zero function''', that always returns zero, in place of the constant function.
# '''Successor function S:''' 
#: <math>S(x) \stackrel{\mathrm{def}}{=}  f(x) = x + 1\,</math>
# '''Projection function''' <math>P_i^k</math> (also called the '''Identity function''' <math>I_i^k</math>): For all natural numbers <math>i, k\,</math> such that <math>1 \le i \le k</math>:
#: <math>P_i^k \stackrel{\mathrm{def}}{=} f(x_1,\ldots,x_k) = x_i</math>.
 
Operators:
 
#  '''Composition operator''' <math>\circ\,</math> (also called the '''substitution operator'''): Given an m-ary function <math>h(x_1,\ldots,x_m)\,</math> and m k-ary functions <math>g_1(x_1,\ldots,x_k),\ldots,g_m(x_1,\ldots, x_k)</math>:
#:<math>h \circ (g_1, \ldots, g_m) \stackrel{\mathrm{def}}{=} f(x_1,\ldots,x_k) = h(g_1(x_1,\ldots,x_k),\ldots,g_m(x_1,\ldots,x_k))\,</math>.
# '''Primitive recursion operator''' <math>\rho\,</math>: Given the k-ary function <math>g(x_1,\ldots,x_k)\,</math> and k+2 -ary function <math>h(y,z,x_1,\ldots,x_k)\,</math>:
#: <math>\begin{align}
            \rho(g, h) &\stackrel{\mathrm{def}}{=} f(y, x_1,\ldots, x_k) \quad {\rm where} \\
    f(0,x_1,\ldots,x_k) &= g(x_1,\ldots,x_k) \\
  f(y+1,x_1,\ldots,x_k) &= h(y,f(y,x_1,\ldots,x_k),x_1,\ldots,x_k)\,\end{align}</math>.
#'''Minimisation operator''' <math>\mu\,</math>: Given a (k+1)-ary total function <math>f(y, x_1, \ldots, x_k)\,</math>:
#:<math>\begin{align}
          \mu(f)(x_1, \ldots, x_k) = z \stackrel{\mathrm{def}}{\iff}\ f(z, x_1, \ldots, x_k)&=0\quad \text{and}\\
            f(i, x_1, \ldots, x_k)&>0 \quad \text{for}\ i=0, \ldots, z-1.
\end{align}</math>
#:Intuitively, minimisation seeks--beginning the search from 0 and proceeding upwards--the smallest argument that causes the function to return zero; if there is no such argument, the search never terminates.
 
The '''strong equality''' operator <math>\simeq</math> can be used to compare partial μ-recursive functions.  This is defined for all partial functions ''f'' and ''g'' so  that
:<math>f(x_1,\ldots,x_k) \simeq g(x_1,\ldots,x_l)</math>
holds if and only if for any choice of arguments either both functions are defined and their values are equal or both functions are undefined.
 
== Equivalence with other models of computability ==
 
{{Expand section|date=February 2010}}
 
In the [[Church's thesis|equivalence of models of computability]], a parallel is drawn between [[Turing machine]]s which do not terminate for certain inputs and an undefined result for that input in the corresponding partial recursive function.
The unbounded search operator is not definable by the rules of primitive recursion as those do not provide a mechanism for "infinite loops" (undefined values).
 
== Normal form theorem ==
 
A [[Kleene's T predicate#Normal form theorem|normal form theorem]] due to Kleene says that for each ''k'' there are primitive recursive functions <math>U(y)\!</math> and <math>T(y,e,x_1,\ldots,x_k)\!</math> such that for any μ-recursive function <math>f(x_1,\ldots,x_k)\!</math> with ''k'' free variables there is an ''e'' such that
:<math>f(x_1,\ldots,x_k) \simeq U(\mu y\, T(y,e,x_1,\ldots,x_k))</math>.
The number ''e'' is called an '''index''' or '''Gödel number''' for the function ''f''.  A consequence of this result is that any μ-recursive function can be defined using a single instance of the μ operator applied to a (total) primitive recursive function.
 
Minsky (1967) observes (as does Boolos-Burgess-Jeffrey (2002) pp.&nbsp;94–95) that the U defined above is in essence the μ-recursive equivalent of the [[universal Turing machine]]:
:To construct U is to write down the definition of a general-recursive function U(n, x) that correctly interprets the number n and computes the appropriate function of x. to construct U directly would involve essentially the same amount of effort, ''and essentially the same ideas'', as we have invested in constructing the universal Turing machine. (italics in original, Minsky (1967) p. 189)
 
== Symbolism ==
A number of different symbolisms are used in the literature. An advantage to using the symbolism is a derivation of a function by "nesting" of the operators one inside the other is easier to write in a compact form. In the following we will abbreviate the string of parameters x<sub>1</sub>, ..., x<sub>n</sub> as '''x''': 
* '''Constant function''': Kleene uses " C<sub>q</sub><sup>n</sup>('''x''') = q " and Boolos-Burgess-Jeffry (2002) (B-B-J) use the abbreviation " const<sub>n</sub>( '''x''') = n ":
:: e.g. C<sub>13</sub><sup>7</sup> ( r, s, t, u, v, w, x ) = 13
:: e.g. const<sub>13</sub> ( r, s, t, u, v, w, x ) = 13
 
* '''Successor function''': Kleene uses x' and S for "Successor". As "successor" is considered to be primitive, most texts use the apostrophe as follows:
:: S(a) = a +1 =<sub>def</sub> a', where 1 =<sub>def</sub>  0', 2 =<sub>def</sub> 0 ' ', etc.
 
* '''Identity function''': Kleene (1952) uses " U<sub>i</sub><sup>n</sup> " to indicate the identity function over the variables x<sub>i</sub>; B-B-J use the identity function id<sub>i</sub><sup>n</sup> over the variables x<sub>1</sub> to x<sub>n</sub>:
: U<sub>i</sub><sup>n</sup>( '''x''' ) = id<sub>i</sub><sup>n</sup>( '''x''' ) = x<sub>i</sub>
: e.g. U<sub>3</sub><sup>7</sup> = id<sub>3</sub><sup>7</sup> ( r, s, t, u, v, w, x ) = t
 
* '''Composition (Substitution) operator''': Kleene uses a bold-face '''S'''<sub>n</sub><sup>m</sup> (not to be confused with his S for "successor" '''!''' ). The superscript "m" refers to the m<sup>th</sup> of function "f<sub>m</sub>", whereas the subscript "n" refers to the n<sup>th</sup> variable "x<sub>n</sub>":
:If we are given h( '''x''' )= g( f<sub>1</sub>('''x'''), ... , f<sub>m</sub>('''x''') )
::  h('''x''') = '''S'''<sub>m</sub><sup>n</sup>(g, f<sub>1</sub>, ... , f<sub>m</sub> )
 
:In a similar manner, but without the sub- and superscripts, B-B-J write:
:: h(''x''')= Cn[g, f<sub>1</sub> ,..., f<sub>m</sub>]('''x''')
 
* '''Primitive Recursion''': Kleene uses the symbol " '''R'''<sup>n</sup>(base step, induction step) " where n indicates the number of variables, B-B-J use " Pr(base step, induction step)('''x''')". Given:
:* base step: h( 0, '''x''' )= f( '''x''' ), and
:* induction step: h( y+1, '''x''' ) = g( y, h(y, '''x'''),'''x''' )
: Example: primitive recursion definition of a + b:
::* base step: f( 0, a ) = a = U<sub>1</sub><sup>1</sup>(a)
::* induction step: f( b' , a ) = ( f ( b, a ) )' = g( b, f( b, a), a ) = g( b, c, a ) = c' = S(U<sub>2</sub><sup>3</sup>( b, c, a )
::: R<sup>2</sup> { U<sub>1</sub><sup>1</sup>(a), S [ (U<sub>2</sub><sup>3</sup>( b, c, a ) ] }
::: Pr{ U<sub>1</sub><sup>1</sup>(a), S[ (U<sub>2</sub><sup>3</sup>( b, c, a ) ] }
 
'''Example''': Kleene gives an example of how to perform the recursive derivation of f(b, a) = b + a (notice reversal of variables a and b). He starting with 3 initial functions
:# S(a) = a'
:# U<sub>1</sub><sup>1</sup>(a) = a
:# U<sub>2</sub><sup>3</sup>( b, c, a ) = c
:# g(b, c, a) = S(U<sub>2</sub><sup>3</sup>( b, c, a )) = c'
:# base step: h( 0, a ) = U<sub>1</sub><sup>1</sup>(a)
:: induction step: h( b', a ) = g( b, h( b, a ), a )
 
He arrives at:
:: a+b = '''R'''<sup>2</sup>[ U<sub>1</sub><sup>1</sup>, '''S'''<sub>1</sub><sup>3</sup>(S, U<sub>2</sub><sup>3</sup>) ]
 
==Examples==
* [[Fibonacci number]]
* [[McCarthy 91 function]]
 
==See also==
*[[Recursion theory]]
* [[Recursion]]
* [[Recursion (computer science)]]
 
==External links==
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/recursive-functions/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry]
 
== References ==
*[[Stephen Kleene]] (1952) ''Introduction to Metamathematics''. Walters-Noordhoff & North-Holland, with corrections (6th imprint 1971); Tenth impression 1991, ISBN 0-7204-2103-9.
*Soare, R.  Recursively enumerable sets and degrees. Springer-Verlag 1987.
*[[Marvin L. Minsky]] (1967), ''Computation: Finite and Infinite Machines'', Prentice-Hall, Inc. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.
:On pages 210-215 Minsky shows how to create the μ-operator using the [[register machine]] model, thus demonstrating its equivalence to the general recursive functions.
*[[George Boolos]], [[John P. Burgess|John Burgess]], [[Richard Jeffrey]] (2002), ''Computability and Logic: Fourth Edition'', Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK. Cf pp.&nbsp;70–71.
 
{{DEFAULTSORT:Mu-Recursive Function}}
[[Category:Computability theory]]
[[Category:Theory of computation]]
 
[[ru:Рекурсивная функция (теория вычислимости)#Частично рекурсивная функция]]

Revision as of 21:48, 21 November 2013

Template:Lowercase In mathematical logic and computer science, the μ-recursive functions are a class of partial functions from natural numbers to natural numbers which are "computable" in an intuitive sense. In fact, in computability theory it is shown that the μ-recursive functions are precisely the functions that can be computed by Turing machines. The μ-recursive functions are closely related to primitive recursive functions, and their inductive definition (below) builds upon that of the primitive recursive functions. However, not every μ-recursive function is a primitive recursive function—the most famous example is the Ackermann function.

Other equivalent classes of functions are the λ-recursive functions and the functions that can be computed by Markov algorithms.

The set of all recursive functions is known as R in computational complexity theory.

Definition

The μ-recursive functions (or partial μ-recursive functions) are partial functions that take finite tuples of natural numbers and return a single natural number. They are the smallest class of partial functions that includes the initial functions and is closed under composition, primitive recursion, and the μ operator.

The smallest class of functions including the initial functions and closed under composition and primitive recursion (i.e. without minimisation) is the class of primitive recursive functions. While all primitive recursive functions are total, this is not true of partial recursive functions; for example, the minimisation of the successor function is undefined. The primitive recursive functions are a subset of the total recursive functions, which are a subset of the partial recursive functions. For example, the Ackermann function can be proven to be total recursive, but not primitive.

Initial or "basic" functions: (In the following the subscripting is per Kleene (1952) p. 219. For more about some of the various symbolisms found in the literature see Symbolism below.)

  1. Constant function: For each natural number and every :
    .
    Alternative definitions use compositions of the successor function and use a zero function, that always returns zero, in place of the constant function.
  2. Successor function S:
  3. Projection function (also called the Identity function ): For all natural numbers such that :
    .

Operators:

  1. Composition operator (also called the substitution operator): Given an m-ary function and m k-ary functions :
    .
  2. Primitive recursion operator : Given the k-ary function and k+2 -ary function :
    .
  3. Minimisation operator : Given a (k+1)-ary total function :
    Intuitively, minimisation seeks--beginning the search from 0 and proceeding upwards--the smallest argument that causes the function to return zero; if there is no such argument, the search never terminates.

The strong equality operator can be used to compare partial μ-recursive functions. This is defined for all partial functions f and g so that

holds if and only if for any choice of arguments either both functions are defined and their values are equal or both functions are undefined.

Equivalence with other models of computability

Template:Expand section

In the equivalence of models of computability, a parallel is drawn between Turing machines which do not terminate for certain inputs and an undefined result for that input in the corresponding partial recursive function. The unbounded search operator is not definable by the rules of primitive recursion as those do not provide a mechanism for "infinite loops" (undefined values).

Normal form theorem

A normal form theorem due to Kleene says that for each k there are primitive recursive functions and such that for any μ-recursive function with k free variables there is an e such that

.

The number e is called an index or Gödel number for the function f. A consequence of this result is that any μ-recursive function can be defined using a single instance of the μ operator applied to a (total) primitive recursive function.

Minsky (1967) observes (as does Boolos-Burgess-Jeffrey (2002) pp. 94–95) that the U defined above is in essence the μ-recursive equivalent of the universal Turing machine:

To construct U is to write down the definition of a general-recursive function U(n, x) that correctly interprets the number n and computes the appropriate function of x. to construct U directly would involve essentially the same amount of effort, and essentially the same ideas, as we have invested in constructing the universal Turing machine. (italics in original, Minsky (1967) p. 189)

Symbolism

A number of different symbolisms are used in the literature. An advantage to using the symbolism is a derivation of a function by "nesting" of the operators one inside the other is easier to write in a compact form. In the following we will abbreviate the string of parameters x1, ..., xn as x:

  • Constant function: Kleene uses " Cqn(x) = q " and Boolos-Burgess-Jeffry (2002) (B-B-J) use the abbreviation " constn( x) = n ":
e.g. C137 ( r, s, t, u, v, w, x ) = 13
e.g. const13 ( r, s, t, u, v, w, x ) = 13
  • Successor function: Kleene uses x' and S for "Successor". As "successor" is considered to be primitive, most texts use the apostrophe as follows:
S(a) = a +1 =def a', where 1 =def 0', 2 =def 0 ' ', etc.
  • Identity function: Kleene (1952) uses " Uin " to indicate the identity function over the variables xi; B-B-J use the identity function idin over the variables x1 to xn:
Uin( x ) = idin( x ) = xi
e.g. U37 = id37 ( r, s, t, u, v, w, x ) = t
  • Composition (Substitution) operator: Kleene uses a bold-face Snm (not to be confused with his S for "successor" ! ). The superscript "m" refers to the mth of function "fm", whereas the subscript "n" refers to the nth variable "xn":
If we are given h( x )= g( f1(x), ... , fm(x) )
h(x) = Smn(g, f1, ... , fm )
In a similar manner, but without the sub- and superscripts, B-B-J write:
h(x')= Cn[g, f1 ,..., fm](x)
  • Primitive Recursion: Kleene uses the symbol " Rn(base step, induction step) " where n indicates the number of variables, B-B-J use " Pr(base step, induction step)(x)". Given:
  • base step: h( 0, x )= f( x ), and
  • induction step: h( y+1, x ) = g( y, h(y, x),x )
Example: primitive recursion definition of a + b:
  • base step: f( 0, a ) = a = U11(a)
  • induction step: f( b' , a ) = ( f ( b, a ) )' = g( b, f( b, a), a ) = g( b, c, a ) = c' = S(U23( b, c, a )
R2 { U11(a), S [ (U23( b, c, a ) ] }
Pr{ U11(a), S[ (U23( b, c, a ) ] }

Example: Kleene gives an example of how to perform the recursive derivation of f(b, a) = b + a (notice reversal of variables a and b). He starting with 3 initial functions

  1. S(a) = a'
  2. U11(a) = a
  3. U23( b, c, a ) = c
  4. g(b, c, a) = S(U23( b, c, a )) = c'
  5. base step: h( 0, a ) = U11(a)
induction step: h( b', a ) = g( b, h( b, a ), a )

He arrives at:

a+b = R2[ U11, S13(S, U23) ]

Examples

See also

External links

References

  • Stephen Kleene (1952) Introduction to Metamathematics. Walters-Noordhoff & North-Holland, with corrections (6th imprint 1971); Tenth impression 1991, ISBN 0-7204-2103-9.
  • Soare, R. Recursively enumerable sets and degrees. Springer-Verlag 1987.
  • Marvin L. Minsky (1967), Computation: Finite and Infinite Machines, Prentice-Hall, Inc. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.
On pages 210-215 Minsky shows how to create the μ-operator using the register machine model, thus demonstrating its equivalence to the general recursive functions.

ru:Рекурсивная функция (теория вычислимости)#Частично рекурсивная функция