Probability interpretations: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>Jochen Burghardt
mentioned Carnap's naming "prob.1" / "prob.2"; to be used as target of REDIRECTs for both names
en>Credence347
 
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Probability fundamentals}}
Hello! My name is Jodie. <br>It is a little about myself: I live in Italy, my city of Malalbergo. <br>It's called often Northern or cultural capital of BO. I've married 2 years ago.<br>I have two children - a son (Verona) and the daughter (Raymundo). We all like Equestrianism.<br>[http://www.eurosummit13.com/content/forevertranscriptioncomlegal-transcription-servicesphp-blank-techniques legal transcription courses]
In Kolmogorov's [[probability theory]], the [[probability]] ''P'' of some [[event (probability theory)|event]] ''E'', denoted <math>P(E)</math>, is usually defined in such a way that ''P'' satisfies the '''Kolmogorov axioms''', named after the famous [[Russia|Russian]] [[mathematician]] [[Andrey Kolmogorov]], which are described below.
 
These assumptions can be summarised as: Let (Ω, ''F'', ''P'') be a [[measure space]] with  ''P''(Ω)=1. Then (Ω, ''F'', ''P'') is a [[probability space]], with sample space Ω, event space ''F'' and probability measure ''P''.
 
An alternative approach to formalising probability, favoured by some [[Bayesian theory|Bayesians]], is given by [[Cox's theorem]].
 
== Axioms ==
 
=== First axiom ===
The probability of an event is a non-negative real number:
:<math>P(E)\in\mathbb{R}, P(E)\geq 0 \qquad \forall E\in F</math>
 
where <math>F</math> is the event space. In particular, <math>P(E)</math> is always finite, in contrast with more general [[measure theory]].  Theories which assign [[negative probability]] relax the first axiom.
 
=== Second axiom ===
{{seealso|Unitarity (physics)}}
This is the assumption of [[unit measure]]: that the probability that some [[elementary event]] in the entire sample space will occur is 1.  More specifically, there are no elementary events outside the sample space.
: <math>P(\Omega) = 1.</math>
 
This is often overlooked in some mistaken probability calculations; if you cannot precisely define the whole sample space, then the probability of any subset cannot be defined either.
 
===Third axiom===
This is the assumption of [[&sigma;-additivity]]:
: Any [[countable]] sequence of [[disjoint sets|disjoint]] (synonymous with ''mutually exclusive'') events <math>E_1, E_2, ...</math> satisfies
::<math>P(E_1 \cup E_2 \cup \cdots) = \sum_{i=1}^\infty P(E_i).</math>
Some authors consider merely [[finitely additive]] probability spaces, in which case one just needs an [[algebra of sets]], rather than a [[&sigma;-algebra]].  [[Quasiprobability distribution]]s in general relax the third axiom.
 
==Consequences==
From the [[Kolmogorov]] axioms, one can deduce other useful rules for calculating probabilities.
 
===Monotonicity===
 
: <math>\quad\text{if}\quad A\subseteq B\quad\text{then}\quad P(A)\leq P(B).</math>
 
===The probability of the empty set===
 
: <math>P(\emptyset)=0.</math>
 
===The numeric bound===
It immediately follows from the monotonicity property that
: <math>0\leq P(E)\leq 1\qquad \text{∀} E\in F.</math>
 
==Proofs==
The proofs of these properties are both interesting and insightful. They illustrate the power of the third axiom,
and its interaction with the remaining two axioms. When studying [[axiomatic]] [[probability theory]], many deep consequences follow from merely these three axioms.
In order to verify the monotonicity property, we set <math>E_1=A</math> and <math>E_2=B\backslash A</math>,
where <math>\quad A\subseteq B \text{ and } E_i=\emptyset</math> for <math>i\geq 3</math>. It is easy to see that the sets <math>E_i</math>
are pairwise disjoint and <math>E_1\cup E_2\cup\ldots=B</math>. Hence,
we obtain from the third axiom that
: <math>P(A)+P(B\backslash A)+\sum_{i=3}^\infty P(\emptyset)=P(B).</math>
Since the left-hand side of this equation is a series of non-negative numbers, and that it converges to
<math>P(B)</math> which is finite, we obtain both <math>P(A)\leq P(B)</math> and <math>P(\emptyset)=0</math>.
The second part of the statement  is seen by contradiction: if <math>P(\emptyset)=a</math> then the left hand side is not less than
: <math>\sum_{i=3}^\infty P(E_i)=\sum_{i=3}^\infty P(\emptyset)=\sum_{i=3}^\infty a = \begin{cases} 0 & \text{if } a=0, \\ \infty & \text{if } a>0. \end{cases}</math>
If <math>a>0</math> then we obtain a contradiction, because the sum does not exceed <math>P(B)</math> which is finite. Thus, <math>a=0</math>. We have shown as a byproduct of the proof of monotonicity that <math>P(\emptyset)=0</math>.
 
==More consequences==
Another important property is:
 
: <math>P(A \cup B) = P(A) + P(B) - P(A \cap B).</math>
 
This is called the addition law of probability, or the sum rule.
That is, the probability that ''A'' ''or'' ''B'' will happen is the sum of the
probabilities that ''A'' will happen and that ''B'' will happen, minus the
probability that both ''A'' ''and'' ''B'' will happen.  This can be extended to the [[inclusion-exclusion principle]].
 
: <math>P(\Omega\setminus E) = 1 - P(E)</math>
 
That is, the probability that any event will ''not'' happen is 1 minus the probability that it will.
 
==Simple example: coin toss==
Consider a single coin-toss, and assume that the coin will either land heads (H) or tails (T) (but not both). No assumption is made as to whether the coin is fair. 
 
We may define:
 
: <math>\Omega = \{H,T\}</math>
: <math>F = \{\emptyset, \{H\}, \{T\}, \{H,T\}\}</math>
 
Kolmogorov's axioms imply that:
 
: <math>P(\emptyset) = 0</math>
The probability of ''neither'' heads ''nor'' tails, is 0.
 
: <math>P(\{H,T\}) = 1</math>
The probability of ''either'' heads ''or'' tails, is 1.
 
: <math>P(\{H\}) + P(\{T\}) = 1</math>
The sum of the probability of heads and the probability of tails, is 1.
 
== See also ==
* [[Law of total probability]]
* [[Measure (mathematics)]]
* [[Borel Algebra]]
* [[Sigma-algebra | σ-Algebra]]
* [[Probability theory]]
* [[Set theory]]
* [[Conditional probability]]
* [[Quasiprobability]]
 
{{No footnotes|date=November 2010}}
 
==Further reading==
* Von Plato, Jan, 2005, "Grundbegriffe der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung" in [[Ivor Grattan-Guinness|Grattan-Guinness, I.]], ed., ''Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics''. Elsevier: 960-69. (in English)
* {{citation|author1=Glenn Shafer|author2=Vladimir Vovk|title=The origins and legacy of Kolmogorov’s Grundbegriffe|url=http://www.probabilityandfinance.com/articles/04.pdf}}
 
==External links==
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/probability-interpret/#KolProCal Kolmogorov`s probability calculus], Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
* [http://mws.cs.ru.nl/mwiki/prob_1.html#M2 Formal definition] of probability in the [[Mizar system]], and the [http://mmlquery.mizar.org/cgi-bin/mmlquery/emacs_search?input=(symbol+Probability+%7C+notation+%7C+constructor+%7C+occur+%7C+th)+ordered+by+number+of+ref list of theorems] formally proved about it.
 
{{DEFAULTSORT:Probability Axioms}}
[[Category:Probability theory]]
[[Category:Mathematical axioms]]

Latest revision as of 19:31, 18 December 2014

Hello! My name is Jodie.
It is a little about myself: I live in Italy, my city of Malalbergo.
It's called often Northern or cultural capital of BO. I've married 2 years ago.
I have two children - a son (Verona) and the daughter (Raymundo). We all like Equestrianism.
legal transcription courses