Main Page: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
No edit summary
No edit summary
Line 1: Line 1:
In [[mathematics]], the '''category of topological spaces''', often denoted '''Top''', is the [[category (category theory)|category]] whose [[object (category theory)|object]]s are [[topological space]]s and whose [[morphism]]s are [[continuous map]]s or some other variant; for example, objects are often assumed to be [[compactly generated space|compactly generated]]. This is a category because the [[function composition|composition]] of two continuous maps is again continuous. The study of '''Top''' and of properties of [[topological space]]s using the techniques of [[category theory]] is known as '''categorical topology'''.
In [[mathematics]], more specifically in the area of [[modern algebra]] known as [[field theory (mathematics)|field theory]], the '''primitive element theorem''' or '''Artin's theorem on primitive elements''' is a result characterizing the finite degree [[field extension]]s that possess a '''primitive element'''. More specifically, the primitive element theorem characterizes those finite degree extensions <math>E\supseteq F</math> such that there exists <math>\alpha\in E</math> with <math>E=F[\alpha]=F(\alpha)</math>.


N.B. Some authors use the name '''Top''' for the category with [[topological manifold]]s as objects and continuous maps as morphisms.
== Terminology ==
Let <math>E\supseteq F</math> be an arbitrary field extension. An element <math>\alpha\in E</math> is said to be a ''primitive element'' for <math>E\supseteq F</math> when


==As a concrete category==
:<math>E=F[\alpha].</math>


Like many categories, the category '''Top''' is a [[concrete category]] (also known as a ''construct''), meaning its objects are [[Set (mathematics)|sets]] with additional structure (i.e. topologies) and its morphisms are [[function (mathematics)|function]]s preserving this structure. There is a natural [[forgetful functor]]
In this situation, the extension <math>E\supseteq F</math> is referred to as a ''[[simple extension]]''. Then every element ''x'' of ''E'' can be written in the form
:''U'' : '''Top''' &rarr; '''Set'''
to the [[category of sets]] which assigns to each topological space the underlying set and to each continuous map the underlying [[function (mathematics)|function]].


The forgetful functor ''U'' has both a [[left adjoint]]
:<math>x=f_{n-1}{\alpha}^{n-1}+\cdots+f_1{\alpha}+f_0</math> where <math>f_i\in F</math>
:''D'' : '''Set''' &rarr; '''Top'''
which equips a given set with the [[discrete topology]] and a [[right adjoint]]
:''I'' : '''Set''' &rarr; '''Top'''
which equips a given set with the [[indiscrete topology]]. Both of these functors are, in fact, [[right inverse]]s to ''U'' (meaning that ''UD'' and ''UI'' are equal to the [[identity functor]] on '''Set'''). Moreover, since any function between discrete or indiscrete spaces is continuous, both of these functors give [[full embedding]]s of '''Set''' into '''Top'''.


The construct '''Top''' is also ''fiber-complete'' meaning that the [[lattice of topologies|category of all topologies]] on a given set ''X'' (called the ''[[fiber (mathematics)|fiber]]'' of ''U'' above ''X'') forms a [[complete lattice]] when ordered by [[set inclusion|inclusion]]. The [[greatest element]] in this fiber is the discrete topology on ''X'' while the [[least element]] is the indiscrete topology.
for all ''i'', and <math>\alpha\in E</math> is fixed. That is, if <math>E\supseteq F</math> is separable of degree ''n'', there exists <math>\alpha\in E</math> such that the set  


The construct '''Top''' is the model of what is called a [[topological category]]. These categories are characterized by the fact that every [[structured source]] <math>(X \to UA_i)_I</math> has a unique [[initial lift]] <math>( A \to A_i)_I</math>. In '''Top''' the initial lift is obtained by placing the [[initial topology]] on the source. Topological categories have many properties in common with '''Top''' (such as fiber-completeness, discrete and indiscrete functors, and unique lifting of limits).
:<math>\{1,\alpha,\cdots,{\alpha}^{n-1}\}</math>  


==Limits and colimits==
is a basis for ''E'' as a [[vector space]] over ''F''.


The category '''Top''' is both [[complete category|complete and cocomplete]], which means that all small [[limit (category theory)|limits and colimit]]s exist in '''Top'''. In fact, the forgetful functor ''U'' : '''Top''' → '''Set''' uniquely lifts both limits and colimits and preserves them as well. Therefore, (co)limits in '''Top''' are given by placing topologies on the corresponding (co)limits in '''Set'''.
For instance, the extensions <math>\mathbb{Q}(\sqrt{2})\supseteq \mathbb{Q}</math> and <math>\mathbb{Q}(x)\supseteq \mathbb{Q}</math> are simple extensions with primitive elements <math>\sqrt{2}</math> and ''x'', respectively (<math>\mathbb{Q}(x)</math> denotes the field of rational functions in the indeterminate ''x'' over <math>\mathbb{Q}</math>).


Specifically, if ''F'' is a [[diagram (category theory)|diagram]] in '''Top''' and  (''L'', φ) is a limit of ''UF'' in '''Set''', the corresponding limit of ''F'' in '''Top''' is obtained by placing the [[initial topology]] on (''L'', φ). Dually, colimits in '''Top''' are obtained by placing the [[final topology]] on the corresponding colimits in '''Set'''.
== Existence statement ==


Unlike many algebraic categories, the forgetful functor ''U'' : '''Top''' → '''Set''' does not create or reflect limits since there will typically be non-universal [[cone (category theory)|cones]] in '''Top''' covering universal cones in '''Set'''.
The interpretation of the theorem changed with the formulation of the theory of [[Emil Artin]], around 1930. From the time of Galois, the role of primitive elements had been to represent a [[splitting field]] as generated by a single element. This (arbitrary) choice of such an element was bypassed in Artin's treatment.<ref>Israel Kleiner, ''A History of Abstract Algebra'' (2007), p. 64.</ref> At the same time, considerations of construction of such an element receded: the theorem becomes an [[existence theorem]].


Examples of limits and colimits in '''Top''' include:
The following theorem of Artin then takes the place of the classical ''primitive element theorem''.


*The [[empty set]] (considered as a topological space) is the [[initial object]] of '''Top'''; any [[singleton (mathematics)|singleton]] topological space is a [[terminal object]]. There are thus no [[zero object]]s in '''Top'''.
;Theorem
*The [[product (category theory)|product]] in '''Top''' is given by the [[product topology]] on the [[Cartesian product]]. The [[coproduct (category theory)|coproduct]] is given by the [[disjoint union (topology)|disjoint union]] of topological spaces.
*The [[equaliser (mathematics)#In category theory|equalizer]] of a pair of morphisms is given by placing the [[subspace topology]] on the set-theoretic equalizer. Dually, the [[coequalizer]] is given by placing the [[quotient topology]] on the set-theoretic coequalizer.
*[[Direct limit]]s and [[inverse limit]]s are the set-theoretic limits with the [[final topology]] and [[initial topology]] respectively.
*[[Adjunction space]]s are an example of [[pushout (category theory)|pushouts]] in '''Top'''.


==Other properties==
Let <math>E\supseteq F</math> be a finite degree field extension. Then <math>E=F[\alpha]</math> for some element <math>\alpha\in E</math> if and only if there exist only finitely many intermediate fields ''K'' with <math>E\supseteq K\supseteq F</math>.
*The [[monomorphism]]s in '''Top''' are the [[injective]] continuous maps, the [[epimorphism]]s are the [[surjective]] continuous maps, and the [[isomorphism]]s are the [[homeomorphism]]s.
*The extremal monomorphisms are (up to isomorphism) the [[subspace topology|subspace]] embeddings. Every extremal monomorphism is [[regular morphism (topology)|regular]].
*The extremal epimorphisms are (essentially) the [[quotient map]]s. Every extremal epimorphism is regular.
*The split monomorphisms are (essentially) the inclusions of [[retract]]s into their ambient space.
*The split epimorphisms are (up to isomorphism) the continuous surjective maps of a space onto one of its retracts.
*There are no [[zero morphism]]s in '''Top''', and in particular the category is not [[preadditive category|preadditive]].
*'''Top''' is not [[cartesian closed category|cartesian closed]] (and therefore also not a [[topos]]) since it does not have [[exponential object]]s for all spaces.


==Relationships to other categories==
A corollary to the theorem is then the primitive element theorem in the more traditional sense (where separability was usually tacitly assumed):


*The category of [[pointed topological space]]s '''Top'''<sub>•</sub> is a [[coslice category]] over '''Top'''.
;Corollary
* The [[homotopy category of topological spaces|homotopy category]] '''hTop''' has topological spaces for objects and [[homotopy equivalent|homotopy equivalence classes]] of continuous maps for morphisms. This is a [[quotient category]] of '''Top'''. One can likewise form the pointed homotopy category '''hTop'''<sub>•</sub>.
*'''Top''' contains the important category '''Haus''' of topological spaces with the [[Hausdorff space|Hausdorff]] property as a [[full subcategory]].  The added structure of this subcategory allows for more epimorphisms:  in fact, the epimorphisms in this subcategory are precisely those morphisms with [[dense set|dense]] [[image (mathematics)|images]] in their [[codomain]]s, so that epimorphisms need not be [[surjective]].


== References ==
Let <math>E\supseteq F</math> be a finite degree [[separable extension]]. Then <math>E=F[\alpha]</math> for some <math>\alpha\in E</math>.


* Herrlich, Horst: ''Topologische Reflexionen und Coreflexionen''. Springer Lecture Notes in Mathematics 78 (1968).
The corollary applies to [[algebraic number field]]s, i.e. finite extensions of the rational numbers '''Q''', since '''Q''' has [[characteristic (algebra)|characteristic]] 0 and therefore every extension over '''Q''' is separable.


* Herrlich, Horst: ''Categorical topology 1971 - 1981''. In: General Topology and its Relations to Modern Analysis and Algebra 5, Heldermann Verlag 1983, pp.&nbsp;279 – 383.
==Counterexamples==


* Herrlich, Horst & Strecker, George E.: Categorical Topology - its origins, as examplified by the unfolding of the theory of topological reflections and coreflections before 1971. In: Handbook of the History of General Topology (eds. C.E.Aull & R. Lowen), Kluwer Acad. Publ. vol 1 (1997) pp.&nbsp;255 – 341.
For non-separable extensions, necessarily in [[characteristic p]] with ''p'' a prime number, then at least when the degree [''L''&nbsp;:&nbsp;''K''] is ''p'', ''L''&nbsp;/&nbsp;''K'' has a primitive element, because there are no intermediate subfields. When [''L''&nbsp;:&nbsp;''K''] = ''p''<sup>2</sup>, there may not be a primitive element (and therefore there are infinitely many intermediate fields). This happens, for example if ''K'' is


* Adámek, Jiří, Herrlich, Horst, & Strecker, George E.; (1990). [http://katmat.math.uni-bremen.de/acc/acc.pdf ''Abstract and Concrete Categories''] (4.2MB PDF). Originally publ. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 0-471-60922-6. (now free on-line edition).
:''F<sub>p</sub>''(''T'',&nbsp;''U''),


[[Category:Category-theoretic categories|Topological spaces]]
the field of rational functions in two indeterminates ''T'' and ''U'' over the [[finite field]] with ''p'' elements, and ''L'' is obtained from ''K'' by adjoining a ''p''-th root of ''T'', and of ''U''. In fact one can see that for any &alpha; in ''L'', the element ''&alpha;''<sup>''p''</sup> lies in ''K'', but a primitive element must have degree ''p''<sup>2</sup> over ''K''.
[[Category:General topology]]
 
==Constructive results==
 
Generally, the set of all primitive elements for a finite separable extension ''L''&nbsp;/&nbsp;''K'' is the complement of a finite collection of proper ''K''-subspaces of&nbsp;''L'', namely the intermediate fields. This statement says nothing for the case of [[finite field]]s, for which there is a computational theory dedicated to finding a generator of the [[multiplicative group]] of the field (a [[cyclic group]]), which is ''a fortiori'' a primitive element. Where ''K'' is infinite, a [[pigeonhole principle]] proof technique considers the linear subspace generated by two elements and proves that there are only finitely many linear combinations
 
:<math>\gamma = \alpha + c \beta\ </math>
 
with ''c'' in ''K'' in it, that fail to generate the subfield containing both elements. This is almost immediate as a way of showing how Artin's result implies the classical result, and a bound for the number of exceptional ''c'' in terms of the number of intermediate fields results (this number being something that can be bounded itself by Galois theory and ''a priori''). Therefore in this case trial-and-error is a possible practical method to find primitive elements. See the Example.
 
== Example ==
It is not, for example, immediately obvious that if one adjoins to the field '''Q''' of [[rational number]]s roots of both [[polynomial]]s
 
:<math>x^2 - 2\ </math>
 
and
 
:<math>x^2 - 3,\ </math>
 
say &alpha; and &beta; respectively, to get a field ''K''&nbsp;=&nbsp;'''Q'''(&alpha;,&nbsp;&beta;) of [[Degree of a field extension|degree]] 4 over '''Q''', that the extension is simple and there exists a primitive element &gamma; in ''K'' so that ''K''&nbsp;=&nbsp;'''Q'''(&gamma;). One can in fact check that with
 
:<math>\gamma = \alpha + \beta\ </math>
 
the powers &gamma;<sup>&nbsp;''i''</sup> for 0&nbsp;&le;&nbsp;''i''&nbsp;&le;&nbsp;3 can be written out as [[linear combination]]s of&nbsp;1,&nbsp;&alpha;,&nbsp;&beta; and ''&alpha;&beta;'' with integer coefficients. Taking these as a [[system of linear equations]], or by factoring, one can solve for &alpha; and &beta; over&nbsp;'''Q'''(''&gamma;'') (one gets, for instance, &alpha;=<math>\scriptstyle\frac{\gamma^3-9\gamma}2</math>), which implies that this choice of &gamma; is indeed a primitive element in this example. A simpler argument, assuming the knowledge of all the subfields as given by Galois theory, is to note the independence of 1,&nbsp;&alpha;,&nbsp;&beta; and &alpha;&beta; over the rationals; this shows that the subfield generated by &gamma; cannot be that generated &alpha; or &beta;, nor in fact that generated by &alpha;&beta;, exhausting all the subfields of degree 2. Therefore it must be the whole field.
 
== See also ==
* [[Primitive element (finite field)]]
 
==References==
 
* [http://www.mathreference.com/fld-sep,pet.html The primitive element theorem at mathreference.com]
* [http://planetmath.org/encyclopedia/ProofOfPrimitiveElementTheorem2.html The primitive element theorem at planetmath.org]
* [http://www.math.cornell.edu/~kbrown/6310/primitive.pdf The primitive element theorem on the site of Cornell's university (pdf file)]
 
==Notes==
{{Reflist}}
 
[[Category:Field theory]]
[[Category:Theorems in abstract algebra]]
 
[[de:Satz vom primitiven Element]]
[[fr:Théorème de l'élément primitif]]
[[it:Teorema dell'elemento primitivo]]
[[pt:Teorema do elemento primitivo]]
[[uk:Теорема про первісний елемент]]
[[zh:本原元定理]]

Revision as of 01:20, 12 August 2014

In mathematics, more specifically in the area of modern algebra known as field theory, the primitive element theorem or Artin's theorem on primitive elements is a result characterizing the finite degree field extensions that possess a primitive element. More specifically, the primitive element theorem characterizes those finite degree extensions such that there exists with .

Terminology

Let be an arbitrary field extension. An element is said to be a primitive element for when

In this situation, the extension is referred to as a simple extension. Then every element x of E can be written in the form

where

for all i, and is fixed. That is, if is separable of degree n, there exists such that the set

is a basis for E as a vector space over F.

For instance, the extensions and are simple extensions with primitive elements and x, respectively ( denotes the field of rational functions in the indeterminate x over ).

Existence statement

The interpretation of the theorem changed with the formulation of the theory of Emil Artin, around 1930. From the time of Galois, the role of primitive elements had been to represent a splitting field as generated by a single element. This (arbitrary) choice of such an element was bypassed in Artin's treatment.[1] At the same time, considerations of construction of such an element receded: the theorem becomes an existence theorem.

The following theorem of Artin then takes the place of the classical primitive element theorem.

Theorem

Let be a finite degree field extension. Then for some element if and only if there exist only finitely many intermediate fields K with .

A corollary to the theorem is then the primitive element theorem in the more traditional sense (where separability was usually tacitly assumed):

Corollary

Let be a finite degree separable extension. Then for some .

The corollary applies to algebraic number fields, i.e. finite extensions of the rational numbers Q, since Q has characteristic 0 and therefore every extension over Q is separable.

Counterexamples

For non-separable extensions, necessarily in characteristic p with p a prime number, then at least when the degree [L : K] is p, L / K has a primitive element, because there are no intermediate subfields. When [L : K] = p2, there may not be a primitive element (and therefore there are infinitely many intermediate fields). This happens, for example if K is

Fp(TU),

the field of rational functions in two indeterminates T and U over the finite field with p elements, and L is obtained from K by adjoining a p-th root of T, and of U. In fact one can see that for any α in L, the element αp lies in K, but a primitive element must have degree p2 over K.

Constructive results

Generally, the set of all primitive elements for a finite separable extension L / K is the complement of a finite collection of proper K-subspaces of L, namely the intermediate fields. This statement says nothing for the case of finite fields, for which there is a computational theory dedicated to finding a generator of the multiplicative group of the field (a cyclic group), which is a fortiori a primitive element. Where K is infinite, a pigeonhole principle proof technique considers the linear subspace generated by two elements and proves that there are only finitely many linear combinations

with c in K in it, that fail to generate the subfield containing both elements. This is almost immediate as a way of showing how Artin's result implies the classical result, and a bound for the number of exceptional c in terms of the number of intermediate fields results (this number being something that can be bounded itself by Galois theory and a priori). Therefore in this case trial-and-error is a possible practical method to find primitive elements. See the Example.

Example

It is not, for example, immediately obvious that if one adjoins to the field Q of rational numbers roots of both polynomials

and

say α and β respectively, to get a field K = Q(α, β) of degree 4 over Q, that the extension is simple and there exists a primitive element γ in K so that K = Q(γ). One can in fact check that with

the powers γ i for 0 ≤ i ≤ 3 can be written out as linear combinations of 1, α, β and αβ with integer coefficients. Taking these as a system of linear equations, or by factoring, one can solve for α and β over Q(γ) (one gets, for instance, α=), which implies that this choice of γ is indeed a primitive element in this example. A simpler argument, assuming the knowledge of all the subfields as given by Galois theory, is to note the independence of 1, α, β and αβ over the rationals; this shows that the subfield generated by γ cannot be that generated α or β, nor in fact that generated by αβ, exhausting all the subfields of degree 2. Therefore it must be the whole field.

See also

References

Notes

43 year old Petroleum Engineer Harry from Deep River, usually spends time with hobbies and interests like renting movies, property developers in singapore new condominium and vehicle racing. Constantly enjoys going to destinations like Camino Real de Tierra Adentro.

de:Satz vom primitiven Element fr:Théorème de l'élément primitif it:Teorema dell'elemento primitivo pt:Teorema do elemento primitivo uk:Теорема про первісний елемент zh:本原元定理

  1. Israel Kleiner, A History of Abstract Algebra (2007), p. 64.