Affine Lie algebra

From formulasearchengine
Revision as of 13:29, 1 December 2013 by 96.33.20.232 (talk) (consistency in ``central extension'' links)
Jump to navigation Jump to search

In computability theory, a machine that always halts—also called a decider (Sipser, 1996) or a total Turing machine (Kozen, 1997)—is a Turing machine that halts for every input.

Because it always halts, the machine is able to decide whether a given string is a member of a formal language. The class of languages which can be decided by such machines is exactly the set of recursive languages. However, due to the Halting Problem, determining whether an arbitrary Turing machine halts on every input is itself an undecidable decision problem.


Functions computable by total Turing machines

In practice, many functions of interest are computable by machines that always halt. A machine that uses only finite memory on any particular input can be forced to halt for every input by restricting its flow control capabilities so that no input will ever cause the machine to enter an infinite loop. As a trivial example, a machine implementing a finitary decision tree will always halt.

It is not required that the machine be entirely free of looping capabilities, however, to guarantee halting. If we restrict loops to be of a predictably finite size (not unlike the FOR loop in BASIC), we can express all of the primitive recursive functions (Meyer and Ritchie, 1967). An example of such a machine is provided by the toy programming language PL-{GOTO} of Brainerd and Landweber (1974).

We can further define a programming language in which we can ensure that even more sophisticated functions always halt. For example, the Ackermann function, which is not primitive recursive, nevertheless is a total computable function computable by a term rewriting system with a reduction ordering on its arguments (Ohlebusch, 2002, pp.67).

Despite the above examples of programming languages which guarantee termination of the programs, there exists no programming language which captures exactly the recursive functions, i.e. the functions which can be computed by a turing machine that always halts. This is due to the fact that existence of such a programming language would be a contradiction to the non-semi-decidability of the problem whether a Turing machine halts on every input.

Relationship to partial Turing machines

A general Turing machine will compute a partial function. Two questions can be asked about the relationship between partial Turing machines and total Turing machines:

  1. Can every partial function computable by a partial Turing machine be extended (that is, have its domain enlarged) to become a total computable function?
  2. Is it possible to change the definition of a Turing machine so that a particular class of total Turing machines, computing all the total computable functions, can be found?

The answer to each of these questions is no.

The following theorem shows that the functions computable by machines that always halt do not include extensions of all partial computable functions, which implies the first question above has a negative answer. This fact is closely related to the algorithmic unsolvability of the Halting problem.

Theorem. There are Turing computable partial functions that have no extension to a total Turing computable function. In particular, the partial function f defined so that f(n) = m if and only if the Turing machine with index n halts on input 0 with output m has no extension to a total computable function.

Indeed, if g were a total computable function extending f then g would be computable by some Turing machine; fix e as the index of such a machine. Build a Turing machine M, using Kleene's recursion theorem, which on input 0 simulates the machine with index e running on an index nM for M (thus the machine M can produce an index of itself; this is the role of the recursion theorem). By assumption, this simulation will eventually return an answer. Define M so that if g(nM) = m then the return value of M is m + 1. Thus f(nM), the true return value of M on input 0, will not equal g(nM). Hence g does not extend f.

The second question asks, in essence, whether there is another reasonable model of computation which computes only total functions and computes all the total computable functions. Informally, if such a model existed then each of its computers could be simulated by a Turing machine. Thus if this new model of computation consisted of a sequence M1,M2, of machines, there would be a recursively enumerable sequence T1,T2, of Turing machines that compute total functions and so that every total computable function is computable by one of the machines Ti. This is impossible, because a machine T could be constructed such that on input i the machine T returns Ti(i)+1. This machine cannot be equivalent to any machine T on the list: suppose it were on the list at index j. Then Tj(j)=Tj(j)+1, which does not return an integer result. Therefore it can't be total, but the function by construction must be total (if total functions are recursively enumerable, then this function can be constructed), so we have a contradiction. This shows that the second question has a negative answer.

The set of indices of total Turing machines

The decision problem of whether the Turing machine with index e will halt on every input is not decidable. In fact, this problem is at level Π20 of the arithmetical hierarchy. Thus this problem is strictly more difficult than the Halting problem, which asks whether the machine with index e halts on input 0. Intuitively, this difference in unsolvability is because each instance of the "total machine" problem represents infinitely many instances of the Halting problem.

See also

References

  • Brainerd, W.S., Landweber, L.H. (1974), Theory of Computation, Wiley.
  • Meyer, A.R., Ritchie, D.M. (1967), The complexity of loop programs, Proc. of the ACM National Meetings, 465.
  • Sipser, M. (1996), Introduction to the Theory of Computation, PWS Publishing Co.
  • Kozen, D.C. (1997), Automata and Computability, Springer.
  • Ohlebusch, E. (2002), Advanced Topics in Term Rewriting, Springer.

Other Sports Official Alfonzo from Chase, has hobbies and interests for instance fast, property developers in new industrial launch singapore and aquariums. In recent times has visited Monasteries of Haghpat and Sanahin.