|
|
Line 1: |
Line 1: |
| In [[mathematical logic]], the '''arithmetical hierarchy''', '''arithmetic hierarchy''' or '''Kleene-Mostowski hierarchy''' classifies certain [[Set (mathematics)|sets]] based on the complexity of formulas that define them. Any set that receives a classification is called '''arithmetical'''.
| |
|
| |
|
| The arithmetical hierarchy is important in [[recursion theory]], [[effective descriptive set theory]], and the study of formal theories such as [[Peano arithmetic]].
| |
|
| |
|
| The [[Tarski-Kuratowski algorithm]] provides an easy way to get an upper bound on the classifications assigned to a formula and the set it defines.
| | Chances are they call me Gabrielle. Vermont also has always been my existing place and I are blessed with everything that I desire here. As a complete girl what I simply like is going on to karaoke but [http://Www.Bing.com/search?q=I+haven%27t&form=MSNNWS&mkt=en-us&pq=I+haven%27t I haven't] made a dime in addition to it. I am a particular cashier and [http://Www.encyclopedia.com/searchresults.aspx?q=I%27m+charging I'm charging] pretty good financially. See what's new on this is my website here: http://prometeu.net<br><br>Feel free to surf to my web page - clash of clans hack cydia ([http://prometeu.net More methods]) |
| | |
| The [[hyperarithmetical hierarchy]] and the [[analytical hierarchy]] extend the arithmetical hierarchy to classify additional formulas and sets.
| |
| | |
| == The arithmetical hierarchy of formulas ==
| |
| | |
| The arithmetical hierarchy assigns classifications to the formulas in the language of [[Peano axioms|first-order arithmetic]]. The classifications are denoted <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> and <math>\Pi^0_n</math> for natural numbers ''n'' (including 0). The Greek letters here are [[lightface]] symbols, which indicates that the formulas do not contain set parameters.
| |
| | |
| If a formula <math>\phi</math> is logically equivalent to a formula with only [[bounded quantifier]]s then <math>\phi</math> is assigned the classifications <math>\Sigma^0_0</math> and <math>\Pi^0_0</math>.
| |
| | |
| The classifications <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> and <math>\Pi^0_n</math> are defined inductively for every natural number ''n'' using the following rules:
| |
| *If <math>\phi</math> is logically equivalent to a formula of the form <math>\exists n_1 \exists n_2\cdots \exists n_k \psi</math>, where <math>\psi</math> is <math>\Pi^0_n</math>, then <math>\phi</math> is assigned the classification <math>\Sigma^0_{n+1}</math>.
| |
| *If <math>\phi</math> is logically equivalent to a formula of the form <math>\forall n_1 \forall n_2\cdots \forall n_k \psi</math>, where <math>\psi</math> is <math>\Sigma^0_n</math>, then <math>\phi</math> is assigned the classification <math>\Pi^0_{n+1}</math>.
| |
| Also, a <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> formula is equivalent to a formula that begins with some [[existential quantifier]]s and alternates <math>n-1</math> times between series of existential and [[universal quantifier]]s; while a <math>\Pi^0_n</math> formula is equivalent to a formula that begins with some universal quantifiers and alternates similarly.
| |
| | |
| Because every formula is equivalent to a formula in [[prenex normal form]], every formula with no set quantifiers is assigned at least one classification. Because redundant quantifiers can be added to any formula, once a formula is assigned the classification <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> or <math>\Pi^0_n</math> it will be assigned the classifications <math>\Sigma^0_m</math> and <math>\Pi^0_m</math> for every ''m'' greater than ''n''. The most important classification assigned to a formula is thus the one with the least ''n'', because this is enough to determine all the other classifications.
| |
| | |
| == The arithmetical hierarchy of sets of natural numbers == | |
| | |
| A set ''X'' of natural numbers is defined by formula φ in the language of [[Peano arithmetic]] if the elements of ''X'' are exactly the numbers that satisfy φ. That is, for all natural numbers ''n'',
| |
| :<math>n \in X \Leftrightarrow \mathbb{N} \models \phi(\underline n),</math>
| |
| where <math>\underline n</math> is the numeral in the language of arithmetic corresponding to <math>n</math>. A set is definable in first order arithmetic if it is defined by some formula in the language of Peano arithmetic.
| |
| | |
| Each set ''X'' of natural numbers that is definable in first order arithmetic is assigned classifications of the form <math>\Sigma^0_n</math>, <math>\Pi^0_n</math>, and <math>\Delta^0_n</math>, where <math>n</math> is a natural number, as follows. If ''X'' is definable by a <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> formula then ''X'' is assigned the classification <math>\Sigma^0_n</math>. If ''X'' is definable by a <math>\Pi^0_n</math> formula then ''X'' is assigned the classification <math>\Pi^0_n</math>. If ''X'' is both <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> and <math>\Pi^0_n</math> then <math>X</math> is assigned the additional classification <math>\Delta^0_n</math>.
| |
| | |
| Note that it rarely makes sense to speak of <math>\Delta^0_n</math> formulas; the first quantifier of a formula is either existential or universal. So a <math>\Delta^0_n</math> set is not defined by a <math>\Delta^0_n</math> formula; rather, there are both <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> and <math>\Pi^0_n</math> formulas that define the set.
| |
| | |
| A parallel definition is used to define the arithmetical hierarchy on finite [[Cartesian power]]s of the natural numbers. Instead of formulas with one free variable, formulas with ''k'' free number variables are used to define the arithmetical hierarchy on sets of ''k''-[[tuple]]s of natural numbers.
| |
| | |
| == Relativized arithmetical hierarchies == | |
| | |
| Just as we can define what it means for a set ''X'' to be [[Recursive set|recursive]] relative to another set ''Y'' by allowing the computation defining ''X'' to consult ''Y'' as an oracle we can extend this notion to the whole arithmetic hierarchy and define what it means for ''X'' to be <math>\Sigma^0_n</math>, <math>\Delta^0_n</math> or <math>\Pi^0_n</math> in ''Y'', denoted respectively <math>\Sigma^{0,Y}_n</math> <math>\Delta^{0,Y}_n</math> and <math>\Pi^{0,Y}_n</math>. To do so, fix a set of integers ''Y'' and add a predicate for membership in ''Y'' to the language of Peano arithmetic. We then say that ''X'' is in <math>\Sigma^{0,Y}_n</math> if it is defined by a <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> formula in this expanded language. In other words ''X'' is <math>\Sigma^{0,Y}_n</math> if it is defined by a <math>\Sigma^{0}_n</math> formula allowed to ask questions about membership in ''Y''. Alternatively one can view the <math>\Sigma^{0,Y}_n</math> sets as those sets that can be built starting with sets recursive in ''Y'' and alternatively [[Projection (set theory)|projecting]] and taking the [[Complement (set theory)|complements]] of these sets up to ''n'' times.
| |
| | |
| For example let ''Y'' be a set of integers. Let ''X'' be the set of numbers divisible by an element of Y. Then ''X'' is defined by the formula <math>\phi(n)=\exists m \exists t (Y(m)\and m\times t = n)</math> so ''X'' is in <math>\Sigma^{0,Y}_1</math> (actually it is in <math>\Delta^{0,Y}_0</math> as well since we could bound both quantifiers by n).
| |
| | |
| == Arithmetic reducibility and degrees ==
| |
| | |
| Arithmetical reducibility is an intermediate notion between [[Turing reducibility]] and [[hyperarithmetic reducibility]].
| |
| | |
| A set is '''arithmetical''' (also '''arithmetic''' and '''arithmetically definable''') if it is defined by some formula in the language of Peano arithmetic. Equivalently ''X'' is arithmetical if ''X'' is <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> or <math>\Pi^0_n</math> for some integer ''n''. A set ''X'' '''is arithmetical in''' a set ''Y'', denoted <math>X \leq_A Y</math>, if ''X'' is definable a some formula in the language of Peano arithmetic extended by a predicate for membership in ''Y''. Equivalently, ''X'' is arithmetical in ''Y'' if ''X'' is in <math>\Sigma^{0,Y}_n</math> or <math>\Pi^{0,Y}_n</math> for some integer ''n''. A synonym for <math>X \leq_A Y</math>is: ''X'' is '''arithmetically reducible''' to ''Y''.
| |
| | |
| The relation <math>X \leq_A Y</math> is reflexive and transitive, and thus the relation <math>\equiv_A</math> defined by the rule
| |
| | |
| :<math> X \equiv_A Y \Leftrightarrow X \leq_A Y \and Y \leq_A X</math>
| |
| is an equivalence relation. The equivalence classes of this relation are called the '''arithmetic degrees'''; they are partially ordered under <math>\leq_A</math>.
| |
| | |
| ==The arithmetical hierarchy of subsets of Cantor and Baire space==
| |
| | |
| The [[Cantor space]], denoted <math>2^{\omega}</math>, is the set of all infinite sequences of 0s and 1s; the [[Baire space (set theory)|Baire space]], denoted <math>\omega^{\omega}</math> or <math>\mathcal{N}</math>, is the set of all infinite sequences of natural numbers. Note that elements of the Cantor space can be identified with sets of integers and elements of the Baire space with functions from integers to integers.
| |
| | |
| The ordinary axiomatization of [[second-order arithmetic]] uses a set-based language in which the set quantifiers can naturally be viewed as quantifying over Cantor space. A subset of Cantor space is assigned the classification <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> if it is definable by a <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> formula. The set is assigned the classification <math>\Pi^0_n</math> if it is definable by a <math>\Pi^0_n</math> formula. If the set is both <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> and <math>\Pi^0_n</math> then it is given the additional classification <math>\Delta^0_n</math>. For example let <math>O\subset 2^{\omega}</math> be the set of all infinite binary strings which aren't all 0 (or equivalently the set of all non-empty sets of integers). As <math>O=\{ X\in 2^\omega | \exists n (X(n)=1) \} </math> we see that <math>O</math> is defined by a <math>\Sigma^0_1</math> formula and hence is a <math>\Sigma^0_1</math> set.
| |
| | |
| Note that while both the elements of the Cantor space (regarded as sets of integers) and subsets of the Cantor space are classified in arithmetic hierarchies but these are not the same hierarchy. In fact the relationship between the two hierarchies is interesting and non-trivial. For instance the <math>\Pi^0_n</math> elements of the Cantor space are not (in general) the same as the elements <math>X</math> of the Cantor space so that <math>\{X\}</math> is a <math>\Pi^0_n</math> subset of the Cantor space. However, many interesting results relate the two hierarchies.
| |
| | |
| There are two ways that a subset of Baire space can be classified in the arithmetical hierarchy.
| |
| *A subset of Baire space has a corresponding subset of Cantor space under the map that takes each function from <math>\omega</math> to <math>\omega</math> to the [[indicator function|characteristic function]] of its graph. A subset of Baire space is given the classification <math>\Sigma^1_n</math>, <math>\Pi^1_n</math>, or <math>\Delta^1_n</math> if and only if the corresponding subset of Cantor space has the same classification.
| |
| *An equivalent definition of the analytical hierarchy on Baire space is given by defining the analytical hierarchy of formulas using a functional version of second-order arithmetic; then the analytical hierarchy on subsets of Cantor space can be defined from the hierarchy on Baire space. This alternate definition gives exactly the same classifications as the first definition.
| |
| | |
| A parallel definition is used to define the arithmetical hierarchy on finite Cartesian powers of Baire space or Cantor space, using formulas with several free variables. The arithmetical hierarchy can be defined on any [[effective Polish space]]; the definition is particularly simple for Cantor space and Baire space because they fit with the language of ordinary second-order arithmetic.
| |
| | |
| Note that we can also define the arithmetic hierarchy of subsets of the Cantor and Baire spaces relative to some set of integers. In fact boldface <math>\bold{\Sigma}^0_n</math> is just the union of <math>\Sigma^{0,Y}_n</math> for all sets of integers ''Y''. Note that the boldface hierarchy is just the standard hierarchy of [[Borel hierarchy|Borel sets]].
| |
| | |
| == Extensions and variations==
| |
| | |
| It is possible to define the arithmetical hierarchy of formulas using a language extended with a function symbol for each [[primitive recursive function]]. This variation slightly changes the classification of some sets.
| |
| | |
| A more semantic variation of the hierarchy can be defined on all finitary relations on the natural numbers; the following definition is used. Every computable relation is defined to be <math>\Sigma^0_0</math> and <math>\Pi^0_0</math>. The classifications <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> and <math>\Pi^0_n</math> are defined inductively with the following rules.
| |
| * If the relation <math>R(n_1,\ldots,n_l,m_1,\ldots, m_k)\,</math> is <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> then the relation <math>S(n_1,\ldots, n_l) = \forall m_1\cdots \forall m_k R(n_1,\ldots,n_l,m_1,\ldots,m_k)</math> is defined to be <math>\Pi^0_{n+1}</math>
| |
| * If the relation <math>R(n_1,\ldots,n_l,m_1,\ldots, m_k)\,</math> is <math>\Pi^0_n</math> then the relation <math>S(n_1,\ldots,n_l) = \exists m_1\cdots \exists m_k R(n_1,\ldots,n_l,m_1,\ldots,m_k)</math> is defined to be <math>\Sigma^0_{n+1}</math>
| |
| This variation slightly changes the classification of some sets. It can be extended to cover finitary relations on the natural numbers, Baire space, and Cantor space.
| |
| | |
| == Meaning of the notation==
| |
| | |
| The following meanings can be attached to the notation for the arithmetical hierarchy on formulas.
| |
| | |
| The subscript <math>n</math> in the symbols <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> and <math>\Pi^0_n</math> indicates the number of alternations of blocks of universal and existential number quantifiers that are used in a formula. Moreover, the outermost block is existential in <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> formulas and universal in <math>\Pi^0_n</math> formulas.
| |
| | |
| The superscript <math>0</math> in the symbols <math>\Sigma^0_n</math>, <math>\Pi^0_n</math>, and <math>\Delta^0_n</math> indicates the type of the objects being quantified over. Type 0 objects are natural numbers, and objects of type <math>i+1</math> are functions that map the set of objects of type <math>i</math> to the natural numbers. Quantification over higher type objects, such as functions from natural numbers to natural numbers, is described by a superscript greater than 0, as in the [[analytical hierarchy]]. The superscript 0 indicates quantifiers over numbers, the superscript 1 would indicate quantification over functions from numbers to numbers (type 1 objects), the superscript 2 would correspond to quantification over functions that take a type 1 object and return a number, and so on.
| |
| | |
| == Examples ==
| |
| | |
| * The <math>\Sigma^0_1</math> sets of numbers are those definable by a formula of the form <math>\exists n_1 \cdots \exists n_k \psi(n_1,\ldots,n_k,m)</math> where <math>\psi</math> has only bounded quantifiers. These are exactly the [[recursively enumerable set]]s.
| |
| | |
| * The set of natural numbers that are indices for Turing machines that compute total functions is <math>\Pi^0_2</math>. Intuitively, an index <math>e</math> falls into this set if and only if for every <math>m</math> "there is an <math>s</math> such that the Turing machine with index <math>e</math> halts on input <math>m</math> after <math>s</math> steps”. A complete proof would show that the property displayed in quotes in the previous sentence is definable in the language of Peano arithmetic by a <math>\Sigma^0_1</math> formula.
| |
| | |
| * Every <math>\Sigma^0_1</math> subset of Baire space or Cantor space is an open set in the usual topology on the space. Moreover, for any such set there is a computable enumeration of Gödel numbers of basic open sets whose union is the original set. For this reason, <math>\Sigma^0_1</math> sets are sometimes called ''effectively open''. Similarly, every <math>\Pi^0_1</math> set is closed and the <math>\Pi^0_1</math> sets are sometimes called ''effectively closed''.
| |
| | |
| * Every arithmetical subset of Cantor space of<sup>(or?)</sup> Baire space is a [[Borel set]]. The lightface Borel hierarchy extends the arithmetical hierarchy to include additional Borel sets. For example, every <math>\Pi^0_2</math> subset of Cantor or Baire space is a <math>G_\delta</math> set (that is, a set which equals the intersection of countably many open sets). Moreover, each of these open sets is <math>\Sigma^0_1</math> and the list of Gödel numbers of these open sets has a computable enumeration. If <math>\phi(X,n,m)</math> is a <math>\Sigma^0_0</math> formula with a free set variable ''X'' and free number variables <math>n,m</math> then the <math>\Pi^0_2</math> set <math>\{X \mid \forall n \exists m \phi(X,n,m)\}</math> is the intersection of the <math>\Sigma^0_1</math> sets of the form <math>\{ X \mid \exists m \phi(X,n,m)\}</math> as ''n'' ranges over the set of natural numbers.
| |
| | |
| == Properties ==
| |
| | |
| The following properties hold for the arithmetical hierarchy of sets of natural numbers and the arithmetical hierarchy of subsets of Cantor or Baire space.
| |
| | |
| * The collections <math>\Pi^0_n</math> and <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> are closed under finite [[union (set theory)|union]]s and finite [[intersection (set theory)|intersection]]s of their respective elements.
| |
| * A set is <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> if and only if its complement is <math>\Pi^0_n</math>. A set is <math>\Delta^0_n</math> if and only if the set is both <math>\Sigma^0_n</math> and <math>\Pi^0_n</math>, in which case its complement will also be <math>\Delta^0_n</math>.
| |
| * The inclusions <math>\Delta^0_n \subsetneq \Pi^0_n</math> and <math>\Delta^0_n \subsetneq \Sigma^0_n</math> hold for <math>n \geq 1</math>.
| |
| * The inclusions <math>\Pi^0_n \subsetneq \Pi^0_{n+1}</math> and <math>\Sigma^0_n \subsetneq \Sigma^0_{n+1}</math> hold for all <math>n</math> and the inclusion <math>\Sigma^0_n \cup \Pi^0_n \subsetneq \Delta^0_{n+1}</math> holds for <math>n \geq 1</math>. Thus the hierarchy does not collapse.
| |
| | |
| == Relation to Turing machines ==
| |
| | |
| The Turing computable sets of natural numbers are exactly the sets at level <math>\Delta^0_1</math> of the arithmetical hierarchy. The recursively enumerable sets are exactly the sets at level <math>\Sigma^0_1</math>.
| |
| | |
| No [[oracle machine]] is capable of solving its own [[halting problem]] (a variation of Turing's proof applies). The halting problem for a <math>\Delta^{0,Y}_n</math> oracle in fact sits in <math>\Sigma^{0,Y}_{n+1}</math>.
| |
| | |
| [[Post's theorem]] establishes a close connection between the arithmetical hierarchy of sets of natural numbers and the [[Turing degree]]s. In particular, it establishes the following facts for all ''n'' ≥ 1: | |
| * The set <math>\emptyset^{(n)}</math> (the ''n''th [[Turing jump]] of the empty set) is [[Many-one reduction|many-one complete]] in <math>\Sigma^0_n</math>.
| |
| * The set <math>\mathbb{N} \setminus \emptyset^{(n)}</math> is many-one complete in <math>\Pi^0_n</math>.
| |
| * The set <math>\emptyset^{(n-1)}</math> is [[Turing complete set|Turing complete]] in <math>\Delta^0_n</math>.
| |
| | |
| The [[polynomial hierarchy]] is a "feasible resource-bounded" version of the arithmetical hierarchy in which polynomial length bounds are placed on the numbers involved (or, equivalently, polynomial time bounds are placed on the Turing machines involved). It gives a finer classification of some sets of natural numbers that are at level <math>\Delta^0_1</math> of the arithmetical hierarchy.
| |
| | |
| == See also ==
| |
| * [[Interpretability logic]]
| |
| * [[Hierarchy (mathematics)]]
| |
| | |
| == References ==
| |
| *{{citation|first=Giorgie|last=Japaridze|title=The logic of arithmetical hierarchy|journal=Annals of Pure and Applied Logic|volume=66|issue=2|year=1994|pages=89–112|doi=10.1016/0168-0072(94)90063-9 | zbl=0804.03045 }}.
| |
| *{{citation|last=Moschovakis|first=Yiannis N. | authorlink=Yiannis N. Moschovakis | title=Descriptive Set Theory | publisher=North Holland | year=1980 | isbn=0-444-70199-0 | zbl=0433.03025 | series=Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics | volume=100 }}.
| |
| *{{citation | last=Nies | first=André | title=Computability and randomness | series=Oxford Logic Guides | volume=51 | location=Oxford | publisher=Oxford University Press | year=2009 | isbn=978-0-19-923076-1 | zbl=1169.03034 }}.
| |
| *{{citation|last=Rogers|first=H., jr | title= Theory of recursive functions and effective computability|publisher=McGraw-Hill | year=1967 | zbl=0183.01401 | location=Maidenhead }}.
| |
| | |
| {{ComplexityClasses}}
| |
| | |
| {{DEFAULTSORT:Arithmetical Hierarchy}}
| |
| [[Category:Mathematical logic hierarchies]]
| |
| [[Category:Computability theory]]
| |
| [[Category:Effective descriptive set theory]]
| |
| [[Category:Hierarchy]]
| |
| [[Category:Complexity classes]]
| |