Square-integrable function: Difference between revisions
en>TjBot m r2.7.2) (Robot: Adding af:Kwadraties integreerbare funksie |
|||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
[[Image:Preference example.jpg|thumb|alt=Example of a preference relation|A simple example of a preference order over three goods]] In [[economics]] and other [[social science]]s, '''preference''' refers to the set of assumptions related to ordering some alternatives, based on the degree of [[happiness]], satisfaction, [[gratification]], enjoyment, or [[utility]] they provide, a process which results in an optimal "[[choice]]" (whether real or theoretical). Although economists are usually not interested in choices or preferences in themselves, they are interested in the theory of choice because it serves as a background for empirical demand analysis.<ref name="Arrow, Kenneth 1958">{{cite journal |last=Arrow |first=Kenneth |year=1958 |title=Utilities, attitudes, choices: a review note |journal=[[Econometrica]] |volume=26 |issue=1 |pages=1–23 |jstor=1907381 }}</ref> | |||
== History == | |||
[[Ragnar Frisch]] was the first to write preference relations using the mathematics of axioms, in 1926.<ref name="Barten 1982 p. 384">Barten, Anton and Volker Böhm. (1982). "Consumer theory", in: Kenneth Arrow and Michael Intrilligator (eds.) ''Handbook of mathematical economics. Vol. II'', p. 384</ref> Up to then, economists had developed an elaborated theory of demand that omitted ''primitive characteristics'' of people. This changed at the end of the 19th and the beginning of the 20th century, when [[logical positivism]] started to affect economics through the notion that any theoretical concept used in a theory should be related to observables.<ref name="econ.hit-u.ac.jp">Gilboa, Itzhak. (2009). [http://www.econ.hit-u.ac.jp/~kmkj/uncertainty/Gilboa_Lecture_Notes.pdf ''Theory of Decision under uncertainty'']. Cambridge: Cambridge university press</ref> Whereas economists in the 18th and 19th centuries felt comfortable theorizing about utility, with the advent of logical positivism in the 20th century, they felt that it needed more of an empirical structure. Because [[binary relation|binary choices]] are directly observable, it instantly appealed to economists. The search for observables in microeconomics is taken even further by [[revealed preference|revealed preference theory]]. | |||
Since the pioneer efforts of Frisch in the 1920s, one of the major issues which has pervaded the theory of preferences is the representability of a preference structure with a real-valued function. This has been achieved by mapping it to the mathematical index called ''utility''. [[Gérard Debreu]], influenced by the ideas of the [[bourbaki|Bourbaki group]], championed the axiomatization of consumer theory in the 1950s, and the tools he borrowed from the mathematical field of binary relations have become mainstream since then. Even though the economics of choice can be examined either at the level of utility functions or at the level of preferences, to move from one to the other can be useful. For example, shifting the conceptual basis from an abstract preference relation to an abstract utility scale results in a new mathematical framework, allowing new kinds of conditions on the structure of preference to be formulated and investigated. | |||
Another historical turnpoint can be traced back to 1895, when [[Georg Cantor]], proved in a theorem that if a binary relation is ''linearly ordered'', then it is also isomorphically embeddable in the ordered real numbers. This notion would become very influential for the theory of preferences in economics: by the 1940s prominent authors such as [[Paul Samuelson]], would theorize about people actually having weakly ordered preferences.<ref>Fishburn, Peter. (1994). "Utility and subjective probability", in: Robert Aumann and Sergiu Hart (eds). ''Handbook of game theory. Vol. 2''. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science. pp. 1397-1435.</ref> | |||
==Basic premises== | |||
In consumer theory, economic actors are thought of as being confronted with a set of possible consumption bundles or commodity space. Of all the available bundles of goods and services, only one is ultimately chosen. The theory of preferences examines the problem of getting to this optimal choice using a ''system of preferences'' within a budgetary limitation. | |||
In reality, people do not necessarily rank or order their preferences in a consistent way. In preference theory, some idealized conditions are regularly imposed on the preferences of economic actors. One of the most important of these idealized conditions is the ''axiom of transitivity'':<ref name="Arrow, Kenneth 1958"/> | |||
If alternative <math>A\!</math> is preferred to alternative <math>B\!</math>, and <math>B\!</math> to <math>C\!</math>, then <math>A\!</math> is preferred to <math>C\!</math>. | |||
The language of binary relations allow one to write down exactly what is meant by "ranked set of preferences", and thus gives an unambiguous definition of ''order''. A preference relation should not be confused with the order relation <math> \geqslant \!</math> used to indicate which of two real numbers is larger.<ref>Binmore, Ken. (1992). ''Fun and games. A text on game theory''. Lexington: Houghton Mifflin</ref> Order relations satisfy an extra condition: | |||
<math>A \geqslant B \!</math>, and <math>B \geqslant A \!</math>, implies <math>A = B \!</math> | |||
which does not always hold in preference relations; hence, an ''indifference relation'' is used in its place (the symbol <math> \sim \!</math> denotes this kind of relation). | |||
A system of preferences or ''preference structure'' refers to the set of qualitative relations between different alternatives of consumption. For example, if the alternatives are: | |||
*Apple | |||
*Orange | |||
*Banana | |||
In this example, a preference structure would be: | |||
"The apple is at least as preferred as the orange", and "The orange is as least as preferred as the Banana". One can use <math>\succsim\!</math> to symbolize that some alternative is "at least as preferred as" another one, which is just a binary relation on the set of alternatives. Therefore: | |||
* Apple <math>\succsim\!</math> Orange | |||
* Orange <math>\succsim\!</math> Banana | |||
The former qualitative relation can be preserved when mapped into a numerical structure, if we impose certain desirable properties over the binary relation: these are the ''axioms of preference order''. For instance: Let us take the apple and assign it the arbitrary number 5.Then take the orange and let us assign it a value lower than 5, since the orange is less preferred than the apple. If this procedure is extended to the banana, one may prove by induction that if <math>u\!</math> is defined on {apple, orange} and it represents a well-defined binary relation called "at least as preferred as" on this set, then it can be extended to a function <math>u\!</math> defined on {apple, orange, banana} and it will represent "at least as preferred as" on this larger set. | |||
Example: | |||
*Apple = 5 | |||
*Orange = 3 | |||
*Banana = 2 | |||
5 > 3 > 2 = u(apple) > u(orange) > u(banana) | |||
and this is consistent with Apple <math>\succsim\!</math> Orange, and with Orange <math>\succsim\!</math> Banana. | |||
===Axioms of order=== | |||
*'''[[total relation|Completeness]]''': for all <math>A\!</math> and <math>B\!</math> we have <math>A\! \succsim\! B\!</math> or <math>B\! \succsim\! A\!</math> or both. | |||
In order for preference theory to be useful mathematically, we need to assume continuity. '''Continuity''' simply means that there are no ‘jumps’ in people’s preferences: if we prefer very large oranges to apples, we will prefer large oranges to apples as well. In mathematical terms, if we prefer point A along a preference curve to point B, points very close to A will also be preferred to B. This allows preference curves to be differentiated. The continuity assumption is "too strong" in the sense that it indeed guarantees the existence of a ''continuous utility function'' representation. Continuity is, therefore, a sufficient condition, but not a necessary one.<ref>{{cite web |url= http://www.policonomics.com/preferences/ |title= Policonomics. Economics made simple|last1= Gallego|first1= Lope|last2= |first2= |year= 2012|work= Preferences |publisher= Open Dictionary|accessdate=16 March 2013}}</ref> | |||
Although some authors include [[reflexive relation|reflexivity]] as one of the axioms required to obtain representability (this axiom states that <math>A\! \succsim\! A\!</math>), it is redundant inasmuch as the completeness axiom implies it already.<ref>[[Andreu Mas-Colell|Mas-Colell, Andreu]], Michael Whinston and Jerry Green (1995). ''Microeconomic theory''. Oxford: Oxford University Press ISBN 0-19-507340-1</ref> | |||
==== Most commonly used axioms ==== | |||
* Order-theoretic: acyclicity, transitivity, the semiorder property, completeness | |||
* Topological: continuity, openness or closedness of the preference sets | |||
* Linear-space: [[convex preferences|convexity]], homogeneity, translation-invariance | |||
=== Normative interpretations of the axioms === | |||
Everyday experience suggests that people at least talk about their preferences as if they had personal "standards of judgment" capable of being applied to the particular domain of alternatives that present themselves from time to time.<ref name="Shapley 1974">Shapley, Lloyd and Martin Shubik. (1974). "Game theory in economics". RAND Report R-904/4</ref> Thus, the axioms are an attempt to model the decision maker's preferences, not over the actual choice, but over the type of desirable procedure (a procedure that any human being would like to follow). [[Behavioral economics]] investigates inconsistent behavior (i.e. behavior that violates the axioms) of people. Believing in axioms in a normative way does not imply that it is mandatory to behave according to them. Instead, they are a mode of behavior suggested; its what people would like to see themselves following.<ref name="econ.hit-u.ac.jp"/> | |||
Here is an illustrative example of the normative implications of the theory of preferences:<ref name="econ.hit-u.ac.jp"/> Consider a decision maker who needs to make a choice. Assume that this is a choice of where to live or whom to marry and that the decision maker has asked an economist for advice. The economist, who wants to engage in normative science, attempts to tell the decision maker how she should make decisions. | |||
Economist: I suggest that you attach a utility index to each alternative, and choose the alternative with the highest utility. | |||
Decision Maker: You've been brainwashed. You think only in terms of functions. But this is an important decision, there are people involved, emotions, these are not functions! | |||
Economist: Would you feel comfortable with cycling among three possible options? Preferring ''x'' to ''y'', and then ''y'' to ''z'', but then again ''z'' to ''x''? | |||
Decision Maker: No, this is very silly and counterproductive. I told you that there are people involved, and I do not want to play with their feelings. | |||
Economist: Good. So now let me tell you a secret: if you follow these two conditions -making decision, and avoid cycling, then you can be described as if you are maximizing a utility function. | |||
Consumers whose preference structures violate transitivity would get exposed to being milked by some unscrupulous person. For instance, Maria prefers apples to oranges, oranges to bananas, and bananas to apples. Let her be endowed with an apple, which she can trade in a market. Because she prefers bananas to apples, she is willing to pay, say, one cent to trade her apple for a banana. Afterwards, Maria is willing to pay another cent to trade her banana for an orange, and again the orange for an apple, and so on. There are [[Intransitivity#Occurrences_in_preferences|other examples]] of this kind of "irrational" behaviour. | |||
Completeness implies that some choice will be made, an assertion that is more philosophically questionable. In most applications, the set of consumption alternatives is infinite and the consumer is not conscious of all preferences. For example, one does not have to choose over going on holiday by plane or by train: if one does not have enough money to go on holiday anyway then it is not necessary to attach a preference order to those alternatives (although it can be nice to dream about what one would do if one would win the lottery). However, preference can be interpreted as a hypothetical choice that could be made rather than a conscious state of mind. In this case, completeness amounts to an assumption that the consumers can always make up their mind whether they are indifferent or prefer one option when presented with any pair of options. | |||
Under some extreme circumstances there is no "rational" choice available. For instance, if asked to choose which one of one's children will be killed, as in [[Sophie's Choice (novel)|Sophie's Choice]], there is no rational way out of it. In that case preferences would be incomplete, since "not being able to choose" is not the same as "being indifferent". | |||
The ''indifference relation'' ~ is an [[equivalence relation]]. Thus we have a [[quotient set]] S/~ of [[equivalence class]]es of S, which forms a [[partition of a set|partition]] of S. Each equivalence class is a set of packages that is equally preferred. | |||
If there are only two commodities, the equivalence classes can be graphically represented as [[indifference curve]]s. | |||
Based on the preference relation on S we have a preference relation on S/~. As opposed to the former, the latter is [[antisymmetric relation|antisymmetric]] and a [[total order]]. | |||
== Applications to theories of utility == | |||
In economics, a utility function is often used to represent a preference structure such that <math>u\left(A\right)\geqslant u(B)</math> [[if and only if]] <math>A \succsim\! B</math>. When a preference order is both transitive and complete, then it is standard practice to call it a ''rational preference relation'', and the people who comply with it are ''rational agents''. A transitive and complete relation is called a [[Strict weak ordering#Total_preorders|''weak order'' (or ''total preorder'')]]. The literature on preferences is far from being standardized regarding terms such as ''complete'', ''partial'', ''strong'', and ''weak''. Together with the terms "total", "linear", "strong complete", "quasi-orders", "pre-orders" and "sub-orders", which also have a different meaning depending on the author's taste, there has been an abuse of semantics in the literature.<ref name="Shapley 1974"/> | |||
According to Simon Board, a [[Continuous function|continuous]] utility function always exists if <math> \succsim\! </math> is a continuous rational preference relation on <math>R^n</math>.<ref name=Boa2005>{{cite web|last=Board|first=Simon|title=Preferences and Utility|url=http://www.econ.ucla.edu/sboard/teaching/econ11_09/econ11_09_lecture2.pdf|publisher=UCLA|accessdate=15 February 2013}}</ref> For any such preference relation, there are many continuous utility functions that represent it. Conversely, every utility function can be used to construct a unique preference relation. | |||
All the above is independent of the prices of the goods and services and of the budget constraints faced by consumers. These determine the ''feasible'' bundles (which they can afford). According to the standard theory, consumers chooses a bundle within their budget such that no other feasible bundle is preferred over it; therefore their utility is maximized. | |||
=== Primitive equivalents of some known properties of utility functions === | |||
* An increasing utility function is associated with a monotonic preference relation. | |||
* [[Quasi-convex function|Quasi-concave]] utility functions are associated with a convex preference order. When non-convex preferences arise, the [[Shapley–Folkman lemma]] is applicable. | |||
* Weakly separable utility functions are associated with the weak separability of preferences. | |||
=== Lexicographic preferences === | |||
[[Lexicographic preferences]] are a special case of preferences that assign an infinite value to a good, when compared with the other goods of a bundle. | |||
== Strict versus weak == | |||
The possibility of defining a strict preference relation <math>\succ\! </math> from the weaker one <math>\succsim\!</math>, and viceversa, suggest in principle an alternative approach of starting with the strict relation <math>\succ\! </math> as the primitive concept and deriving the weaker one and the indifference relation. However, an indifference relation derived this way will generally not be transitive.<ref name="Barten 1982 p. 384"/> According to Kreps "beginning with strict preference makes it easier to discuss noncomparability possibilities".<ref>{{cite book|last=Kreps|first=David|title=A Course in Microeconomic Theory|year=1990|publisher=Princeton University Press|location=New Jersey|isbn=0-691-04264-0|page=24}}</ref> | |||
== Aggregation == | |||
Under certain assumptions, individual preferences can be aggregated onto the preferences of a group of people. As a result of agreggation, [[Arrow's impossibility theorem]] states that voting systems sometimes can not convert individual preferences into desirable community-wide acts of choice. | |||
== Expected utility theory == | |||
Preference relations can also be applied to a space of simple lotteries, as in [[expected utility hypothesis|expected utility theory]]. In this case a preference structure over lotteries can also be represented by a utility function. | |||
== Criticism == | |||
Some critics say that rational theories of choice and preference theories rely too heavily on the assumption of invariance, which states that the relation of preference should not depend on the description of the options or on the method of elicitation. But without this assumption, one's preferences cannot be represented as maximization of utility.<ref>Slovic, P. (1995). "The Construction of Preference". American Psychologist, Vol. 50, No. 5, pp. 364-371.</ref> | |||
==See also== | |||
*[[Behavioral economics]] | |||
*[[Convex preferences]] | |||
*[[Economic subjectivism]] | |||
*[[Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem]] | |||
*[[Lexicographic preferences]] | |||
*[[Pairwise comparison]] | |||
*[[Revealed preference]] | |||
*[[Strict weak ordering]] | |||
*[[Time preference]] | |||
== References == | |||
{{Reflist}} | |||
*Kreps, David (1990). ''A Course in Microeconomic Theory''. New Jersey: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-04264-0 | |||
{{microeconomics-footer}} | |||
{{DEFAULTSORT:Preference (Economics)}} | |||
[[Category:Microeconomics]] | |||
[[Category:Consumer theory]] |
Revision as of 16:40, 7 January 2014
In economics and other social sciences, preference refers to the set of assumptions related to ordering some alternatives, based on the degree of happiness, satisfaction, gratification, enjoyment, or utility they provide, a process which results in an optimal "choice" (whether real or theoretical). Although economists are usually not interested in choices or preferences in themselves, they are interested in the theory of choice because it serves as a background for empirical demand analysis.[1]
History
Ragnar Frisch was the first to write preference relations using the mathematics of axioms, in 1926.[2] Up to then, economists had developed an elaborated theory of demand that omitted primitive characteristics of people. This changed at the end of the 19th and the beginning of the 20th century, when logical positivism started to affect economics through the notion that any theoretical concept used in a theory should be related to observables.[3] Whereas economists in the 18th and 19th centuries felt comfortable theorizing about utility, with the advent of logical positivism in the 20th century, they felt that it needed more of an empirical structure. Because binary choices are directly observable, it instantly appealed to economists. The search for observables in microeconomics is taken even further by revealed preference theory.
Since the pioneer efforts of Frisch in the 1920s, one of the major issues which has pervaded the theory of preferences is the representability of a preference structure with a real-valued function. This has been achieved by mapping it to the mathematical index called utility. Gérard Debreu, influenced by the ideas of the Bourbaki group, championed the axiomatization of consumer theory in the 1950s, and the tools he borrowed from the mathematical field of binary relations have become mainstream since then. Even though the economics of choice can be examined either at the level of utility functions or at the level of preferences, to move from one to the other can be useful. For example, shifting the conceptual basis from an abstract preference relation to an abstract utility scale results in a new mathematical framework, allowing new kinds of conditions on the structure of preference to be formulated and investigated.
Another historical turnpoint can be traced back to 1895, when Georg Cantor, proved in a theorem that if a binary relation is linearly ordered, then it is also isomorphically embeddable in the ordered real numbers. This notion would become very influential for the theory of preferences in economics: by the 1940s prominent authors such as Paul Samuelson, would theorize about people actually having weakly ordered preferences.[4]
Basic premises
In consumer theory, economic actors are thought of as being confronted with a set of possible consumption bundles or commodity space. Of all the available bundles of goods and services, only one is ultimately chosen. The theory of preferences examines the problem of getting to this optimal choice using a system of preferences within a budgetary limitation.
In reality, people do not necessarily rank or order their preferences in a consistent way. In preference theory, some idealized conditions are regularly imposed on the preferences of economic actors. One of the most important of these idealized conditions is the axiom of transitivity:[1]
If alternative is preferred to alternative , and to , then is preferred to .
The language of binary relations allow one to write down exactly what is meant by "ranked set of preferences", and thus gives an unambiguous definition of order. A preference relation should not be confused with the order relation used to indicate which of two real numbers is larger.[5] Order relations satisfy an extra condition:
which does not always hold in preference relations; hence, an indifference relation is used in its place (the symbol denotes this kind of relation).
A system of preferences or preference structure refers to the set of qualitative relations between different alternatives of consumption. For example, if the alternatives are:
- Apple
- Orange
- Banana
In this example, a preference structure would be:
"The apple is at least as preferred as the orange", and "The orange is as least as preferred as the Banana". One can use to symbolize that some alternative is "at least as preferred as" another one, which is just a binary relation on the set of alternatives. Therefore:
The former qualitative relation can be preserved when mapped into a numerical structure, if we impose certain desirable properties over the binary relation: these are the axioms of preference order. For instance: Let us take the apple and assign it the arbitrary number 5.Then take the orange and let us assign it a value lower than 5, since the orange is less preferred than the apple. If this procedure is extended to the banana, one may prove by induction that if is defined on {apple, orange} and it represents a well-defined binary relation called "at least as preferred as" on this set, then it can be extended to a function defined on {apple, orange, banana} and it will represent "at least as preferred as" on this larger set.
Example:
- Apple = 5
- Orange = 3
- Banana = 2
5 > 3 > 2 = u(apple) > u(orange) > u(banana)
and this is consistent with Apple Orange, and with Orange Banana.
Axioms of order
- Completeness: for all and we have or or both.
In order for preference theory to be useful mathematically, we need to assume continuity. Continuity simply means that there are no ‘jumps’ in people’s preferences: if we prefer very large oranges to apples, we will prefer large oranges to apples as well. In mathematical terms, if we prefer point A along a preference curve to point B, points very close to A will also be preferred to B. This allows preference curves to be differentiated. The continuity assumption is "too strong" in the sense that it indeed guarantees the existence of a continuous utility function representation. Continuity is, therefore, a sufficient condition, but not a necessary one.[6]
Although some authors include reflexivity as one of the axioms required to obtain representability (this axiom states that ), it is redundant inasmuch as the completeness axiom implies it already.[7]
Most commonly used axioms
- Order-theoretic: acyclicity, transitivity, the semiorder property, completeness
- Topological: continuity, openness or closedness of the preference sets
- Linear-space: convexity, homogeneity, translation-invariance
Normative interpretations of the axioms
Everyday experience suggests that people at least talk about their preferences as if they had personal "standards of judgment" capable of being applied to the particular domain of alternatives that present themselves from time to time.[8] Thus, the axioms are an attempt to model the decision maker's preferences, not over the actual choice, but over the type of desirable procedure (a procedure that any human being would like to follow). Behavioral economics investigates inconsistent behavior (i.e. behavior that violates the axioms) of people. Believing in axioms in a normative way does not imply that it is mandatory to behave according to them. Instead, they are a mode of behavior suggested; its what people would like to see themselves following.[3]
Here is an illustrative example of the normative implications of the theory of preferences:[3] Consider a decision maker who needs to make a choice. Assume that this is a choice of where to live or whom to marry and that the decision maker has asked an economist for advice. The economist, who wants to engage in normative science, attempts to tell the decision maker how she should make decisions.
Economist: I suggest that you attach a utility index to each alternative, and choose the alternative with the highest utility.
Decision Maker: You've been brainwashed. You think only in terms of functions. But this is an important decision, there are people involved, emotions, these are not functions!
Economist: Would you feel comfortable with cycling among three possible options? Preferring x to y, and then y to z, but then again z to x?
Decision Maker: No, this is very silly and counterproductive. I told you that there are people involved, and I do not want to play with their feelings.
Economist: Good. So now let me tell you a secret: if you follow these two conditions -making decision, and avoid cycling, then you can be described as if you are maximizing a utility function.
Consumers whose preference structures violate transitivity would get exposed to being milked by some unscrupulous person. For instance, Maria prefers apples to oranges, oranges to bananas, and bananas to apples. Let her be endowed with an apple, which she can trade in a market. Because she prefers bananas to apples, she is willing to pay, say, one cent to trade her apple for a banana. Afterwards, Maria is willing to pay another cent to trade her banana for an orange, and again the orange for an apple, and so on. There are other examples of this kind of "irrational" behaviour.
Completeness implies that some choice will be made, an assertion that is more philosophically questionable. In most applications, the set of consumption alternatives is infinite and the consumer is not conscious of all preferences. For example, one does not have to choose over going on holiday by plane or by train: if one does not have enough money to go on holiday anyway then it is not necessary to attach a preference order to those alternatives (although it can be nice to dream about what one would do if one would win the lottery). However, preference can be interpreted as a hypothetical choice that could be made rather than a conscious state of mind. In this case, completeness amounts to an assumption that the consumers can always make up their mind whether they are indifferent or prefer one option when presented with any pair of options.
Under some extreme circumstances there is no "rational" choice available. For instance, if asked to choose which one of one's children will be killed, as in Sophie's Choice, there is no rational way out of it. In that case preferences would be incomplete, since "not being able to choose" is not the same as "being indifferent".
The indifference relation ~ is an equivalence relation. Thus we have a quotient set S/~ of equivalence classes of S, which forms a partition of S. Each equivalence class is a set of packages that is equally preferred. If there are only two commodities, the equivalence classes can be graphically represented as indifference curves. Based on the preference relation on S we have a preference relation on S/~. As opposed to the former, the latter is antisymmetric and a total order.
Applications to theories of utility
In economics, a utility function is often used to represent a preference structure such that if and only if . When a preference order is both transitive and complete, then it is standard practice to call it a rational preference relation, and the people who comply with it are rational agents. A transitive and complete relation is called a weak order (or total preorder). The literature on preferences is far from being standardized regarding terms such as complete, partial, strong, and weak. Together with the terms "total", "linear", "strong complete", "quasi-orders", "pre-orders" and "sub-orders", which also have a different meaning depending on the author's taste, there has been an abuse of semantics in the literature.[8]
According to Simon Board, a continuous utility function always exists if is a continuous rational preference relation on .[9] For any such preference relation, there are many continuous utility functions that represent it. Conversely, every utility function can be used to construct a unique preference relation.
All the above is independent of the prices of the goods and services and of the budget constraints faced by consumers. These determine the feasible bundles (which they can afford). According to the standard theory, consumers chooses a bundle within their budget such that no other feasible bundle is preferred over it; therefore their utility is maximized.
Primitive equivalents of some known properties of utility functions
- An increasing utility function is associated with a monotonic preference relation.
- Quasi-concave utility functions are associated with a convex preference order. When non-convex preferences arise, the Shapley–Folkman lemma is applicable.
- Weakly separable utility functions are associated with the weak separability of preferences.
Lexicographic preferences
Lexicographic preferences are a special case of preferences that assign an infinite value to a good, when compared with the other goods of a bundle.
Strict versus weak
The possibility of defining a strict preference relation from the weaker one , and viceversa, suggest in principle an alternative approach of starting with the strict relation as the primitive concept and deriving the weaker one and the indifference relation. However, an indifference relation derived this way will generally not be transitive.[2] According to Kreps "beginning with strict preference makes it easier to discuss noncomparability possibilities".[10]
Aggregation
Under certain assumptions, individual preferences can be aggregated onto the preferences of a group of people. As a result of agreggation, Arrow's impossibility theorem states that voting systems sometimes can not convert individual preferences into desirable community-wide acts of choice.
Expected utility theory
Preference relations can also be applied to a space of simple lotteries, as in expected utility theory. In this case a preference structure over lotteries can also be represented by a utility function.
Criticism
Some critics say that rational theories of choice and preference theories rely too heavily on the assumption of invariance, which states that the relation of preference should not depend on the description of the options or on the method of elicitation. But without this assumption, one's preferences cannot be represented as maximization of utility.[11]
See also
- Behavioral economics
- Convex preferences
- Economic subjectivism
- Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem
- Lexicographic preferences
- Pairwise comparison
- Revealed preference
- Strict weak ordering
- Time preference
References
43 year old Petroleum Engineer Harry from Deep River, usually spends time with hobbies and interests like renting movies, property developers in singapore new condominium and vehicle racing. Constantly enjoys going to destinations like Camino Real de Tierra Adentro.
- Kreps, David (1990). A Course in Microeconomic Theory. New Jersey: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-04264-0
Template:Microeconomics-footer
- ↑ 1.0 1.1 One of the biggest reasons investing in a Singapore new launch is an effective things is as a result of it is doable to be lent massive quantities of money at very low interest rates that you should utilize to purchase it. Then, if property values continue to go up, then you'll get a really high return on funding (ROI). Simply make sure you purchase one of the higher properties, reminiscent of the ones at Fernvale the Riverbank or any Singapore landed property Get Earnings by means of Renting
In its statement, the singapore property listing - website link, government claimed that the majority citizens buying their first residence won't be hurt by the new measures. Some concessions can even be prolonged to chose teams of consumers, similar to married couples with a minimum of one Singaporean partner who are purchasing their second property so long as they intend to promote their first residential property. Lower the LTV limit on housing loans granted by monetary establishments regulated by MAS from 70% to 60% for property purchasers who are individuals with a number of outstanding housing loans on the time of the brand new housing purchase. Singapore Property Measures - 30 August 2010 The most popular seek for the number of bedrooms in Singapore is 4, followed by 2 and three. Lush Acres EC @ Sengkang
Discover out more about real estate funding in the area, together with info on international funding incentives and property possession. Many Singaporeans have been investing in property across the causeway in recent years, attracted by comparatively low prices. However, those who need to exit their investments quickly are likely to face significant challenges when trying to sell their property – and could finally be stuck with a property they can't sell. Career improvement programmes, in-house valuation, auctions and administrative help, venture advertising and marketing, skilled talks and traisning are continuously planned for the sales associates to help them obtain better outcomes for his or her shoppers while at Knight Frank Singapore. No change Present Rules
Extending the tax exemption would help. The exemption, which may be as a lot as $2 million per family, covers individuals who negotiate a principal reduction on their existing mortgage, sell their house short (i.e., for lower than the excellent loans), or take part in a foreclosure course of. An extension of theexemption would seem like a common-sense means to assist stabilize the housing market, but the political turmoil around the fiscal-cliff negotiations means widespread sense could not win out. Home Minority Chief Nancy Pelosi (D-Calif.) believes that the mortgage relief provision will be on the table during the grand-cut price talks, in response to communications director Nadeam Elshami. Buying or promoting of blue mild bulbs is unlawful.
A vendor's stamp duty has been launched on industrial property for the primary time, at rates ranging from 5 per cent to 15 per cent. The Authorities might be trying to reassure the market that they aren't in opposition to foreigners and PRs investing in Singapore's property market. They imposed these measures because of extenuating components available in the market." The sale of new dual-key EC models will even be restricted to multi-generational households only. The models have two separate entrances, permitting grandparents, for example, to dwell separately. The vendor's stamp obligation takes effect right this moment and applies to industrial property and plots which might be offered inside three years of the date of buy. JLL named Best Performing Property Brand for second year running
The data offered is for normal info purposes only and isn't supposed to be personalised investment or monetary advice. Motley Fool Singapore contributor Stanley Lim would not personal shares in any corporations talked about. Singapore private home costs increased by 1.eight% within the fourth quarter of 2012, up from 0.6% within the earlier quarter. Resale prices of government-built HDB residences which are usually bought by Singaporeans, elevated by 2.5%, quarter on quarter, the quickest acquire in five quarters. And industrial property, prices are actually double the levels of three years ago. No withholding tax in the event you sell your property. All your local information regarding vital HDB policies, condominium launches, land growth, commercial property and more
There are various methods to go about discovering the precise property. Some local newspapers (together with the Straits Instances ) have categorised property sections and many local property brokers have websites. Now there are some specifics to consider when buying a 'new launch' rental. Intended use of the unit Every sale begins with 10 p.c low cost for finish of season sale; changes to 20 % discount storewide; follows by additional reduction of fiftyand ends with last discount of 70 % or extra. Typically there is even a warehouse sale or transferring out sale with huge mark-down of costs for stock clearance. Deborah Regulation from Expat Realtor shares her property market update, plus prime rental residences and houses at the moment available to lease Esparina EC @ Sengkang - ↑ 2.0 2.1 Barten, Anton and Volker Böhm. (1982). "Consumer theory", in: Kenneth Arrow and Michael Intrilligator (eds.) Handbook of mathematical economics. Vol. II, p. 384
- ↑ 3.0 3.1 3.2 Gilboa, Itzhak. (2009). Theory of Decision under uncertainty. Cambridge: Cambridge university press
- ↑ Fishburn, Peter. (1994). "Utility and subjective probability", in: Robert Aumann and Sergiu Hart (eds). Handbook of game theory. Vol. 2. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science. pp. 1397-1435.
- ↑ Binmore, Ken. (1992). Fun and games. A text on game theory. Lexington: Houghton Mifflin
- ↑ Template:Cite web
- ↑ Mas-Colell, Andreu, Michael Whinston and Jerry Green (1995). Microeconomic theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press ISBN 0-19-507340-1
- ↑ 8.0 8.1 Shapley, Lloyd and Martin Shubik. (1974). "Game theory in economics". RAND Report R-904/4
- ↑ Template:Cite web
- ↑ 20 year-old Real Estate Agent Rusty from Saint-Paul, has hobbies and interests which includes monopoly, property developers in singapore and poker. Will soon undertake a contiki trip that may include going to the Lower Valley of the Omo.
My blog: http://www.primaboinca.com/view_profile.php?userid=5889534 - ↑ Slovic, P. (1995). "The Construction of Preference". American Psychologist, Vol. 50, No. 5, pp. 364-371.