|
|
Line 1: |
Line 1: |
| {{Economics sidebar}}
| | My name is Sandra Dunbabin. I life in Kastrup (Denmark).<br><br>My homepage [http://hemorrhoidtreatmentfix.com/hemorrhoid-symptoms symptoms of hemorrhoids] |
| '''Marginalism''' is a theory of [[economics]] that attempts to explain the discrepancy in the value of goods and services by reference to their secondary, or marginal, utility. The reason why the price of diamonds is higher than that of water, for example, owes to the greater additional satisfaction of the diamonds over the water. Thus, while the water has greater total utility, the diamond has greater [[marginal utility]].<ref>Rhoads, Steven E.; [http://www.econlib.org/library/Enc/Marginalism.html “Marginalism”,] ''Concise Encyclopedia of Economics''. Liberty Fund, Inc. Ed. David R. Henderson. Library of Economics and Liberty, 17 July 2007.</ref> The theory has been used in order to explain the difference in wages among essential and non-essential services, such as why the wages of an air-conditioner repairman exceed those of a childcare worker.<ref>{{cite web|last=Henderson|first=David|title=Why Repairmen Earn More Than Child-Care Workers|url=http://www.econlib.org/library/Enc/Marginalism.html|work=The Concise Encyclopedia of Economics|publisher=Library of Economics and Liberty|accessdate=2 July 2012}}</ref>
| |
| | |
| The theory arose in the mid-to-late nineteenth century in response to the normative practice of [[classical economics]] and growing socialist debates about social and economic activity. Marginalism was an attempt to raise the discipline of economics to the level of objectivity and universalism so that it would not be beholden to normative critiques.<ref name="Unger, Roberto Mangabeira 1987. pp. 120–122">Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 1987. Social Theory: Its Situation and Its Task. New York: Verso, pp. 120–122.</ref> The theory has since come under attack for its failure to understand the nature of the market and for its inability to account for new empirical data.<ref name="Unger, Roberto Mangabeira 1987. pp. 123–125">Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 1987. Social Theory: Its Situation and Its Task. New York: Verso, pp. 123–125.</ref>
| |
| | |
| Although the central concept of marginalism is that of [[marginal utility]], marginalists, following the lead of [[Alfred Marshall]], drew upon the idea of [[Marginal product|marginal physical productivity]] in explanation of [[cost]]. The [[Neoclassical economics|neoclassical]] tradition that emerged from [[United Kingdom of Great Britain and Ireland|British]] marginalism abandoned the concept of [[utility]] and gave [[Marginal rate of substitution|marginal rates of substitution]] a more fundamental role in analysis.{{citation needed|date=February 2012}} Marginalism is an integral part of [[mainstream economics|mainstream economic]] theory.
| |
| | |
| == Important marginal concepts ==
| |
| === Marginality ===
| |
| Constraints are conceptualized as a ''border'' or ''margin''.<ref>[[Philip Wicksteed|Wicksteed, Philip Henry]]; [http://www.econlib.org/library/Wicksteed/wkCS.html ''The Common Sense of Political Economy'' (1910),] [http://www.econlib.org/cgi-bin/searchbooks.pl?searchtype=BookSearchPara&id=wkCS&query=margin Bk I Ch 2 and elsewhere].</ref> The location of the margin for any individual corresponds to his or her ''endowment'', broadly conceived to include opportunities. This endowment is determined by many things including physical laws (which constrain how forms of energy and matter may be transformed), accidents of nature (which determine the presence of natural resources), and the outcomes of past decisions made both by others and by the individual.
| |
| | |
| A value that holds true given particular constraints is a [[marginal value|''marginal'' value]]. A change that would be affected as or by a specific loosening or tightening of those constraints is a ''marginal'' change.
| |
| | |
| Neoclassical economics usually assumes that marginal changes are [[infinitesimal]]s or [[Limit (mathematics)|limits]]. (Though this assumption makes the analysis less robust, it increases tractability.) One is therefore often told that “marginal” is synonymous with “very small”, though in more general analysis this may not be operationally true (and would not in any case be literally true). Frequently, economic analysis concerns the marginal values associated with a change of one unit of a resource, because decisions are often made in terms of units; marginalism seeks to explain unit prices in terms of such marginal values.
| |
| | |
| === Marginal use ===
| |
| {{main|Marginal use}}
| |
| The '''marginal use''' of a [[Good (economics)|good or service]] is the specific use to which an agent would put a given increase, or the specific use of the good or service that would be abandoned in response to a given decrease.<ref name="wieser_ein">von Wieser, Friedrich; ''Über den Ursprung und die Hauptgesetze des wirtschaftlichen Wertes'' <nowiki>[</nowiki>''The Nature and Essence of Theoretical Economics''<nowiki>]</nowiki> (1884), p. 128.</ref>
| |
| | |
| Marginalism assumes, for any given agent, [[Rational choice theory|economic rationality]] and an [[Order theory|ordering]] of possible states-of-the-world, such that, for any given set of constraints, there is an attainable state which is best in the eyes of that agent. [[Positive science|Descriptive]] marginalism asserts that choice amongst the specific means by which various anticipated specific states-of-the-world (outcomes) might be affected is governed only by the distinctions amongst those specific outcomes; [[Normative economics|prescriptive]] marginalism asserts that such choice ''ought'' to be so governed.
| |
| | |
| On such assumptions, each increase would be put to the specific, feasible, previously unrealized use of greatest priority, and each decrease would result in abandonment of the use of lowest priority amongst the uses to which the good or service had been put.<ref name="wieser_ein" />
| |
| | |
| === Marginal utility ===
| |
| {{main|Marginal utility}}
| |
| The '''marginal utility''' of a good or service is the utility of its [[marginal use]]. Under the assumption of economic rationality, it is the utility of its least urgent possible use ''from'' the best feasible combination of actions in which its use is included.
| |
| | |
| In 20th century [[mainstream economics]], the term “[[utility]]” has come to be formally ''defined'' as a ''[[Measure (mathematics)|quantification]]'' capturing preferences by assigning greater quantities to states, goods, services, or applications that are of higher priority. But marginalism and the concept of marginal utility predate the establishment of this convention within economics. The more general conception of utility is that of ''use'' or ''usefulness'', and this conception is at the heart of marginalism; the term “marginal utility” arose from translation of the German “Grenznutzen”,<ref name="wieser_ein" /><ref name="wieser_zwei">von Wieser, Friedrich; ''Der natürliche Werth'' <nowiki>[</nowiki>''Natural Value''<nowiki>]</nowiki> (1889) , Bk I Ch V “Marginal Utility” ([http://praxeology.net/FW-NV-I-5.htm HTML]).</ref> which literally means ''border use'', referring directly to the marginal use, and the more general formulations of marginal utility do not treat quantification as an ''essential'' feature.<ref name="mc_culloch">Mc Culloch, James Huston; “The Austrian Theory of the Marginal Use and of Ordinal Marginal Utility”, ''[[Zeitschrift für Nationalökonomie]]'' 37 (1973) #3&4 (September).</ref> On the other hand, none of the early marginalists insisted that utility were ''not'' quantified,<ref>[[George Stigler|Stigler, George Joseph]]; “The Development of Utility Theory” ''[[Journal of Political Economy]]'' (1950).</ref><ref>[[George Stigler|Stigler, George Joseph]]; “The Adoption of Marginal Utility Theory” ''History of Political Economy'' (1972).</ref> some indeed treated quantification as an essential feature, and those who did not still used an assumption of quantification for expository purposes. In this context, it is not surprising to find many presentations that fail to recognize a more general approach.
| |
| | |
| ==== Quantified marginal utility ====
| |
| Under the [[special case]] in which usefulness can be quantified, the change in utility of moving from state <math>S_1</math> to state <math>S_2</math> is
| |
| :<math>\Delta U=U(S_2)-U(S_1)\,</math>
| |
| Moreover, if <math>S_1</math> and <math>S_2</math> are distinguishable by values of just one variable <math>g\,</math> which is itself quantified, then it becomes possible to speak of the ratio of the marginal utility of the change in <math>g\,</math> to the size of that change:
| |
| :<math>\left.\frac{\Delta U}{\Delta g}\right|_{c.p.}</math>
| |
| (where “[[ceteris paribus|c.p.]]” indicates that the ''only'' [[Dependent and independent variables|independent variable]] to change is <math>g\,</math>).
| |
| | |
| Mainstream neoclassical economics will typically assume that
| |
| :<math>\lim_{\Delta g\to 0}{\left.\frac{\Delta U}{\Delta g}\right|_{c.p.}}</math>
| |
| is well defined, and use “marginal utility” to refer to a [[partial derivative]]
| |
| :<math>\frac{\partial U}{\partial g}\approx\left.\frac{\Delta U}{\Delta g}\right|_{c.p.}</math>
| |
| | |
| ==== The “law” of diminishing marginal utility ====
| |
| The “law” of diminishing marginal utility (also known as a “[[Hermann Heinrich Gossen|Gossen]]'s First Law”) is that, ''[[ceteris paribus]]'', as additional amounts of a good or service are added to available resources, their marginal utilities are decreasing. This “law” is sometimes treated as a [[tautology (logic)|tautology]], sometimes as something proven by introspection, or sometimes as a mere [[Instrumentalism|instrumental]] assumption, adopted only for its perceived predictive efficacy. Actually, it is not quite any of these things, though it may have aspects of each. The “law” does not hold under all circumstances, so it is neither a tautology nor otherwise proveable; but it has a basis in prior observation.
| |
| | |
| An individual will typically be able to [[Partially ordered set|partially order]] the potential uses of a good or service. If there is [[scarcity]], then a rational agent will satisfy wants of highest possible priority, so that no want is avoidably sacrificed to satisfy a want of ''lower'' priority. In the absence of complementarity across the uses, this will imply that the priority of use of any additional amount will be lower than the priority of the established uses, as in this famous example:
| |
| :A pioneer farmer had five sacks of grain, with no way of selling them or buying more. He had five possible uses: as basic feed for himself, food to build strength, food for his chickens for dietary variation, an ingredient for making whisky and feed for his parrots to amuse him. Then the farmer lost one sack of grain. Instead of reducing every activity by a fifth, the farmer simply starved the parrots as they were of less utility than the other four uses; in other words they were on the margin. And it is on the margin, and not with a view to the big picture, that we make economic decisions.<ref name="bawerk_capital">Böhm-Bawerk, Eugen Ritter von; ''Kapital Und Kapitalizns. Zweite Abteilung: Positive Theorie des Kapitales'' (1889). Translated as ''Capital and Interest. II: Positive Theory of Capital'' with appendices rendered as ''Further Essays on Capital and Interest''.</ref>
| |
| [[Image:Marginal-utility.png|thumb|right|Diminishing marginal utility, given quantification]]
| |
| However, if there ''is'' a complementarity across uses, then an amount added can bring things past a desired tipping point, or an amount subtracted cause them to fall short. In such cases, the marginal utility of a good or service might actually be ''increasing''.
| |
| | |
| Without the presumption that utility is quantified, the ''diminishing'' of utility should not be taken to be itself an [[Elementary arithmetic|arithmetic]] [[subtraction]]. It is the movement from use of higher to lower priority, and may be no more than a purely [[Ranking|ordinal]] change.<ref name="mc_culloch" /><ref name="georgescu-rogen">[[Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen|Theodore-Angwenyi, Nicholas]]; “Utility”, ''International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences'' (1968).</ref>
| |
| | |
| When quantification of utility is assumed, diminishing marginal utility corresponds to a utility function whose ''[[slope]]'' is continually or continuously decreasing. In the latter case, if the function is also smooth, then the “law” may be expressed
| |
| :<math>\frac{\partial^2 U}{\partial g^2}<0</math>
| |
| Neoclassical economics usually supplements or supplants discussion of marginal utility with [[indifference curve]]s, which were originally derived as the [[level curve]]s of utility functions,<ref name="edgeworth">Edgeworth, Francis Ysidro; [http://socserv.mcmaster.ca/econ/ugcm/3ll3/edgeworth/mathpsychics.pdf ''Mathematical Psychics''] (1881).</ref> or can be produced without presumption of quantification,<ref name="mc_culloch" /> but are often simply treated as axiomatic. In the absence of complementarity of goods or services, diminishing marginal utility implies [[Convex function|convexity]] of indifference curves<ref name="mc_culloch" /><ref name="edgeworth" /> (though such convexity would also follow from [[quasiconcavity]] of the utility function).
| |
| | |
| === Marginal rate of substitution ===
| |
| {{Main|Marginal rate of substitution}}
| |
| The ''rate of substitution'' is the ''least favorable'' rate at which an agent is willing to exchange units of one good or service for units of another. The '''''marginal''''' '''rate of substitution''' (“MRS”) is the rate of substitution at the margin — in other words, given some constraint(s).
| |
| | |
| When goods and services are [[Discrete mathematics|discrete]], the least favorable rate at which an agent would trade A for B will usually be different from that at which she would trade B for A:
| |
| :<math>MRS_{AB} \neq \frac1{MRS_{BA}}</math>
| |
| But, when the goods and services are continuously divisible, in the [[limiting case]]
| |
| :<math>MRS_{AB} = \frac1{MRS_{BA}}</math>
| |
| and the marginal rate of substitution is the slope of the [[indifference curve]] (multiplied by <math>-1</math>).
| |
| | |
| If, for example, Lisa will not trade a goat for anything less than two sheep, then her
| |
| :<math>MRS_{SG} = \frac{2\text{ sheep}}\text{goat}</math>
| |
| And if she will not trade a sheep for anything less than two goats, then her
| |
| :<math>MRS_{GS} = \frac{2\text{ goat}}\text{sheep} \neq \frac{1\text{ goat}}{2\text{ sheep}} = \frac1{\left(\frac{2\text{ sheep}}\text{goat}\right)} = \frac1{MRS_{SG}}</math>
| |
| But if she would trade one gram of banana for one ounce of ice cream ''and vice versa'', then
| |
| :<math>MRS_{IB} = \frac{1\text{ oz ice cream}}{1\text{ g banana}} = \frac1{\left(\frac{1\text{ g banana}}{1\text{ oz ice cream}}\right)} = \frac1{MRS_{BI}}</math>
| |
| | |
| When indifference curves (which are essentially graphs of instantaneous rates of substitution) and the convexity of those curves are not taken as given, the “law” of diminishing marginal utility is invoked to explain diminishing marginal rates of substitution — a willingness to accept fewer units of good or service <math>A</math> in substitution for <math>B</math> as one's holdings of <math>A</math> grow relative to those of <math>B</math>. If an individual has a stock or flow of a good or service whose marginal utility is less than would be that of some other good or service for which he or she could trade, then it is in his or her interest to effect that trade. Of course, as one thing is traded-away and another is acquired, the respective marginal gains or losses from further trades are now changed. On the assumption that the marginal utility of one is diminishing, and the other is not increasing, all else being equal, an individual will demand an increasing ratio of that which is acquired to that which is sacrificed. (One important way in which all else might not be equal is when the use of the one good or service complements that of the other. In such cases, exchange ratios might be constant.<ref name="mc_culloch" />) If any trader can better his or her own marginal position by offering an exchange more favorable to other traders with desired goods or services, then he or she will do so.
| |
| | |
| === Marginal cost ===
| |
| {{Main|Marginal cost}}
| |
| At the highest level of generality, a '''marginal cost''' is a marginal [[opportunity cost]]. In most contexts, however, “marginal cost” will refer to marginal ''[[Money|pecuniary]]'' cost — that is to say marginal cost measured by forgone money.
| |
| | |
| A thorough-going marginalism sees marginal cost as increasing under the “law” of diminishing marginal utility, because applying resources to one application reduces their availability to other applications. Neoclassical economics tends to disregard this argument, but to see marginal costs as increasing in consequence of [[diminishing returns]].
| |
| | |
| == Application to price theory ==
| |
| Marginalism and neoclassical economics typically explain price formation broadly through the interaction of [[supply and demand|curves or schedules of supply and demand]]. In any case buyers are modelled as pursuing typically lower quantities, and sellers offering typically higher quantities, as price is increased, with each being willing to trade until the marginal value of what they would trade-away exceeds that of the thing for which they would trade.
| |
| | |
| === Demand ===
| |
| Demand curves are explained by marginalism in terms of marginal rates of substitution.
| |
| | |
| At any given price, a prospective buyer has some marginal rate of substitution of money for the good or service in question. Given the “law” of diminishing marginal utility, or otherwise given convex indifference curves, the rates are such that the willingness to forgo money for the good or service decreases as the buyer would have ever more of the good or service and ever less money. Hence, any given buyer has a demand schedule that generally decreases in response to price (at least until quantity demanded reaches zero). The aggregate quantity demanded by all buyers is, at any given price, just the sum of the quantities demanded by individual buyers, so it too decreases as price increases.
| |
| | |
| === Supply ===
| |
| Both neoclassical economics and thorough-going marginalism could be said to explain supply curves in terms of marginal cost; however, there are marked differences in conceptions of that cost.
| |
| | |
| Marginalists in the tradition of [[Alfred Marshall|Marshall]] and neoclassical economists tend to represent the supply curve for any producer as a curve of marginal pecuniary costs objectively determined by physical processes, with an upward slope determined by [[diminishing returns]].
| |
| | |
| A more thorough-going marginalism represents the supply curve as a ''complementary demand curve'' — where the demand is ''for'' money and the purchase is made ''with'' a good or service.<ref name="schumMarshScis">Schumpeter, Joseph Alois; ''History of Economic Analysis'' (1954) Pt IV Ch 6 §4.</ref> The shape of that curve is then determined by marginal rates of substitution of money for that good or service.
| |
| | |
| === Markets ===
| |
| By confining themselves to limiting cases in which sellers or buyers are both “price takers” — so that demand functions ignore supply functions or ''vice versa'' — Marshallian marginalists and neoclassical economists produced tractable models of [[Perfect competition|“pure” or “perfect” competition]] and of various forms of [[Imperfect competition|“imperfect” competition]], which models are usually captured by relatively simple graphs. Other marginalists have sought to present what they thought of as more realistic explanations,<ref>Mund, Vernon Arthur; ''Monopoly: A History and Theory'' (1933).</ref><ref>[[Mises, Ludwig Heinrich Edler von]]; [http://library.mises.org/books/Ludwig%20von%20Mises/Nationalokonomie%20Theorie%20des%20Handelns%20und%20Wirtschaftens.pdf ''Nationalökonomie: Theorie des Handelns und Wirtschaftens''] (1940). (See also his [http://mises.org/books/humanaction.pdf ''Human Action''.])</ref> but this work has been relatively uninfluential on the mainstream of economic thought.
| |
| | |
| === The paradox of water and diamonds ===
| |
| {{main|Paradox of value}}
| |
| The “law” of diminishing marginal utility is said to explain the “paradox of water and diamonds”, most commonly associated with [[Adam Smith]]<ref>Smith, Adam; ''An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations'' (1776) Chapter IV. “Of the Origin and Use of Money”.</ref> (though recognized by earlier thinkers).<ref>{{cite book|first = Scott|last = Gordon|year = 1991|title = History and Philosophy of Social Science: An Introduction|chapter = The Scottish Enlightenment of the eighteenth century|publisher = [[Routledge]]|isbn = 0-415-09670-7}}</ref> Human beings cannot even survive without water, whereas diamonds, in Smith's day, were ornamentation or engraving bits. Yet water had a very small price, and diamonds a very large price. Marginalists explained that it is the ''marginal'' usefulness of any given quantity that matters, rather than the usefulness of a ''class'' or of a ''totality''. For most people, water was sufficiently abundant that the loss or gain of a gallon would withdraw or add only some very minor use if any, whereas diamonds were in much more restricted supply, so that the loss or gain was much greater.
| |
| | |
| That is not to say that the price of any good or service is simply a function of the marginal utility that it has for any one individual nor for some ostensibly typical individual. Rather, individuals are willing to trade based upon the respective marginal utilities of the goods that they have or desire (with these marginal utilities being distinct for each potential trader), and prices thus develop constrained by these marginal utilities.
| |
| | |
| == History ==
| |
| {{Expand section|date=June 2008}}
| |
| | |
| === Proto-marginalist approaches ===
| |
| Perhaps the essence of a notion of diminishing marginal utility can be found in [[Aristotle]]'s [[Politics (Aristotle)|''Politics'']], whereïn he writes {{Quotation|external goods have a limit, like any other instrument, and all things useful are of such a nature that where there is too much of them they must either do harm, or at any rate be of no use<ref>[[Aristotle]], ''Politics'', Bk 7 Chapter 1.</ref>}}
| |
| | |
| (There has been marked disagreement about the development and role of marginal considerations in Aristotle's' value theory.<ref>Soudek, Josef; “Aristotle's Theory of Exchange: An Inquiry into the Origin of Economic Analysis”, ''Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society'' v 96 (1952) pp. 45–75.</ref><ref name="kauder">Kauder, Emil; “Genesis of the Marginal Utility Theory from Aristotle to the End of the Eighteenth Century”, ''Economic Journal'' v 63 (1953) pp. 638–50.</ref><ref>Gordon, Barry Lewis John; “Aristotle and the Development of Value Theory”, ''Quarterly Journal of Economics'' v 78 (1964).</ref><ref name="schumArist">Schumpeter, Joseph Alois; ''History of Economic Analysis'' (1954) Part II Chapter 1 §3.</ref><ref>Meikle, Scott; ''Aristotle's Economic Thought'' (1995) Chapters 1, 2, & 6.</ref>)
| |
| | |
| A great variety of economists concluded that there was ''some'' sort of inter-relationship between utility and rarity that effected economic decisions, and in turn informed the determination of prices.<ref>[[Karl Přibram|Přibram, Karl]]; ''A History of Economic Reasoning'' (1983).</ref>
| |
| | |
| Eighteenth-century Italian [[Mercantilism|mercantilists]], such as [[Antonio Genovesi]], [[Giammaria Ortes]], [[Pietro Verri]], [[Cesare Beccaria]], and [[Giovanni Rinaldo]], held that value was explained in terms of the general utility and of scarcity, though they did not typically work-out a theory of how these interacted.<ref name="pribramItalMerc">Pribram, Karl; ''A History of Economic Reasoning'' (1983), Chapter 5 “Refined Mercantilism”, “Italian Mercantilists”.</ref> In ''Della moneta'' (1751), Abbé [[Ferdinando Galiani]], a pupil of Genovesi, attempted to explain value as a ratio of two ratios, ''utility'' and ''scarcity'', with the latter component ratio being the ratio of quantity to use.
| |
| | |
| [[Anne Robert Jacques Turgot]], in ''Réflexions sur la formation et la distribution de richesse'' (1769), held that value derived from the general utility of the class to which a good belonged, from comparison of present and future wants, and from anticipated difficulties in procurement.
| |
| | |
| Like the Italian mercantists, [[Étienne Bonnot de Condillac]] saw value as determined by utility associated with the class to which the good belong, and by estimated scarcity. In ''De commerce et le gouvernement'' (1776), Condillac emphasized that value is not based upon cost but that costs were paid because of value.
| |
| | |
| This last point was famously restated by the Nineteenth Century proto-marginalist, [[Richard Whately]], who in ''Introductory Lectures on Political Economy'' (1832) wrote {{Quotation|It is not that pearls fetch a high price because men have dived for them; but on the contrary, men dive for them because they fetch a high price.<ref>Whately, Richard; ''Introductory Lectures on Political Economy, Being part of a course delivered in the Easter term'' (1832).</ref>}} (Whately's student [[Nassau William Senior]] is noted below as an early marginalist.)
| |
| | |
| === Marginalists before the Revolution ===
| |
| The first unambiguous published statement of any sort of theory of marginal utility was by [[Daniel Bernoulli]], in “Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis”.<ref>Bernoulli, Daniel; “Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis” in ''Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae'' 5 (1738); reprinted in translation as “Exposition of a new theory on the measurement of risk” in ''Econometrica'' 22 (1954).</ref> This paper appeared in 1738, but a draft had been written in 1731 or in 1732.<ref>Bernoulli, Daniel; letter of 4 July 1731 to Nicolas Bernoulli ([http://www.cs.xu.edu/math/Sources/Montmort/stpetersburg.pdf#search=%22Nicolas%20Bernoulli%22 excerpted in PDF]).</ref><ref>Bernoulli, Nicolas; letter of 5 April 1732, acknowledging receipt of “Specimen theoriae novae metiendi sortem pecuniariam” ([http://www.cs.xu.edu/math/Sources/Montmort/stpetersburg.pdf#search=%22Nicolas%20Bernoulli%22 excerpted in PDF]).</ref> In 1728, [[Gabriel Cramer]] produced fundamentally the same theory in a private letter.<ref>Cramer, Garbriel; letter of 21 May 1728 to [[Nicolaus I Bernoulli|Nicolaus Bernoulli]] ([http://www.cs.xu.edu/math/Sources/Montmort/stpetersburg.pdf#search=%22Nicolas%20Bernoulli%22 excerpted in PDF]).</ref> Each had sought to resolve the [[St. Petersburg paradox]], and had concluded that the marginal desirability of money decreased as it was accumulated, more specifically such that the desirability of a sum were the [[natural logarithm]] (Bernoulli) or [[square root]] (Cramer) thereof. However, the more general implications of this hypothesis were not explicated, and the work fell into obscurity.
| |
| | |
| In [http://socserv2.socsci.mcmaster.ca/~econ/ugcm/3ll3/lloyd/value “A Lecture on the Notion of Value as Distinguished Not Only from Utility, but also from Value in Exchange”], delivered in 1833 and included in ''Lectures on Population, Value, Poor Laws and Rent'' (1837), [[William Forster Lloyd]] explicitly offered a general marginal utility theory, but did not offer its derivation nor elaborate its implications. The importance of his statement seems to have been lost on everyone (including Lloyd) until the early 20th century, by which time others had independently developed and popularized the same insight.<ref>[[Edwin Robert Anderson Seligman|Seligman, Edwin Robert Anderson]]; “On some neglected British economists”, ''Economic Journal'' v. 13 (September 1903).</ref>
| |
| | |
| In ''An Outline of the Science of Political Economy'' (1836), [[Nassau William Senior]] asserted that marginal utilities were the ultimate determinant of demand, yet apparently did not pursue implications, though some interpret his work as indeed doing just that.<ref>White, Michael V; “Diamonds Are Forever(?): Nassau Senior and Utility Theory” in ''The Manchester School of Economic & Social Studies'' 60 (1992) #1 (March).</ref>
| |
| | |
| In “De la mesure de l’utilité des travaux publics” (1844), [[Jules Dupuit]] applied a conception of marginal utility to the problem of determining bridge tolls.<ref>Dupuit, Jules; “De la mesure de l’utilité des travaux publics”, ''Annales des ponts et chaussées'', Second series, 8 (1844).</ref>
| |
| | |
| In 1854, [[Hermann Heinrich Gossen]] published ''Die Entwicklung der Gesetze des menschlichen Verkehrs und der daraus fließenden Regeln für menschliches Handeln'', which presented a marginal utility theory and to a very large extent worked-out its implications for the behavior of a market economy. However, Gossen's work was not well received in the Germany of his time, most copies were destroyed unsold, and he was virtually forgotten until rediscovered after the so-called Marginal Revolution.
| |
| | |
| === The Marginal Revolution ===
| |
| Marginalism as a formal theory can be attributed to the work of three economists, [[William Stanley Jevons|Jevons]] in England, [[Carl Menger|Menger]] in Austria, and [[Léon Walras|Walras]] in Switzerland.{{citation needed|date=July 2012}} [[William Stanley Jevons]] first proposed the theory in articles in 1863 and 1871.<ref>[http://socserv2.socsci.mcmaster.ca/~econ/ugcm/3ll3/jevons/mathem.txt “A General Mathematical Theory of Political Economy”] ([http://www.eco.utexas.edu/~hmcleave/jevonsmath.pdf PDF]), ''The Theory of Political Economy'' (1871).</ref> Similarly, [[Carl Menger]] presented the theory in 1871.<ref>''Grundsätze der Volkswirtschaftslehre'' (translated as [http://mises.org/document/595 ''Principles of Economics'' PDF])</ref> Menger explained why individuals use marginal utility to decide amongst trade-offs, but while his illustrative examples present utility as quantified, his essential assumptions do not.{{vague|date=July 2012}}<ref name="georgescu-rogen"/>
| |
| [[Léon Walras]] introduced the theory in ''Éléments d'économie politique pure'', the first part of which was published in 1874. (American [[John Bates Clark]] is also associated with the origins of Marginalism, but he did little to advance the theory.{{citation needed|date=July 2012}}
| |
| | |
| This moment in the late 19th century marked a turning point in economy theory. With the introduction of these theories, the analysis of production and exchange turned away from social theory and towards the quest of a scientific objectivity. Classical economics had focused on the causal relations among social activities, which were connected with the production and distribution of wealth. Classical economists asked questions about the true basis of value, activities that contributed to national wealth, systems of rights, or about the forms of government under which people grow rich. But in the late 19th century, in response to attacks from socialists and debates about how society works, and as a means to escape the conundrums of value theory and to answer how values could become prices, economists developed the theory of marginalism. This disengaged economics from descriptive and normative commitments with the aim to withdraw economics from debates about how society worked and what kind of society we wanted to live in, and escalate it to an objective and universal realm.<ref name="Unger, Roberto Mangabeira 1987. pp. 120–122">Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 1987. Social Theory: Its Situation and Its Task. New York: Verso, pp. 120–122.</ref><ref>Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 2007. Free Trade Reimagined: The World Division of Labor and the Method of Economics. Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 55–64.</ref>
| |
| | |
| ==== The second generation ====
| |
| Although the Marginal Revolution flowed from the work of Jevons, Menger, and Walras, their work might have failed to enter the mainstream were it not for a second generation of economists. In England, the second generation were exemplified by [[Philip Wicksteed]], by [[William Smart (economist)|William Smart]], and by [[Alfred Marshall]]; in Austria by [[Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk]] and by [[Friedrich von Wieser]]; in Switzerland by [[Vilfredo Pareto]]; and in America by [[Herbert Joseph Davenport]] and by [[Frank Fetter|Frank A. Fetter]].
| |
| | |
| There were significant, distinguishing features amongst the approaches of Jevons, Menger, and Walras, but the second generation did not maintain distinctions along national or linguistic lines. The work of von Wieser was heavily influenced by that of Walras. Wicksteed was heavily influenced by Menger. Fetter referred to himself and Davenport as part of “the American Psychological School”, named in imitation of the Austrian “Psychological School”. (And Clark's work from this period onward similarly shows heavy influence by Menger.) William Smart began as a conveyor of Austrian School theory to English-language readers, though he fell increasingly under the influence of Marshall.<ref name="salerno">Salerno, Joseph T. 1999; “The Place of Mises’s Human Action in the Development of Modern Economic Thought.” ''Quarterly Journal of Economic Thought'' v. 2 (1).</ref>
| |
| | |
| Böhm-Bawerk was perhaps the most able expositor of Menger's conception.<ref name="salerno" /><ref>Böhm-Bawerk, Eugen Ritter von. “Grundzüge der Theorie des wirtschaftlichen Güterwerthes”, ''Jahrbüche für Nationalökonomie und Statistik'' v 13 (1886). Translated as ''Basic Principles of Economic Value''.</ref> He was further noted for producing a theory of interest and of profit in equilibrium based upon the interaction of diminishing marginal utility with diminishing [[marginal product]]ivity of time and with [[time preference]].<ref name="bawerk_capital"/> (This theory was adopted in full and then further developed by [[Knut Wicksell]]<ref>Wicksell, Johan Gustaf Knut; ''Über Wert, Kapital unde Rente'' (1893). Translated as [http://mises.org/books/valuecapital.pdf ''Value, Capital and Rent''.]</ref> and, with modifications including formal disregard for time-preference, by Wicksell's American rival [[Irving Fisher]].<ref>Fisher, Irving; ''Theory of Interest'' (1930).</ref>)
| |
| | |
| Marshall was the second-generation marginalist whose work on marginal utility came most to inform the mainstream of neoclassical economics, especially by way of his ''Principles of Economics'', the first volume of which was published in 1890. Marshall constructed the demand curve with the aid of assumptions that utility was quantified, and that the marginal utility of money was constant (or nearly so). Like Jevons, Marshall did not see an explanation for supply in the theory of marginal utility, so he synthesized an explanation of demand thus explained with supply explained in a more [[Classical economics|classical]] manner, determined by costs which were taken to be objectively determined. (Marshall later actively mischaracterized the criticism that these costs were themselves ultimately determined by marginal utilities.<ref name="schumMarshScis" />)
| |
| | |
| ==== The Marginal Revolution and Marxism ====
| |
| Although the doctrines of marginalism and the Marginal Revolution are often interpreted as a response to [[Marxism|Marxist economics]],<ref name="screpanti">Screpanti, Ernesto, and Stefano Zamagni; ''An Outline of the History of Economic Thought'' (1994).</ref> the first volume of ''[[Das Kapital]]'' was not published until July 1867, after the works of Jevons, Menger, and Walras were written or well under way.{{Citation needed|date=September 2011}} [[Friedrich Hayek|Hayek]] and [[William Warren Bartley|Bartley]] speculate that Marx may have come across the works of one or more of these figures, and that his inability to formulate a viable critique may account for his failure to complete ''Kapital''.<ref>Hayek, Friedrich August von, with [[William Warren Bartley]]; ''The Fatal Conceit: The Errors of Socialism'' (1988) p150.</ref>
| |
| | |
| Scholars have suggested that the success of the generation who followed the preceptors of the Revolution was their ability to formulate straightforward responses to Marxist economic theory.<ref name="screpanti" /> The most famous of these was that of Böhm-Bawerk, “Zum Abschluss des Marxschen Systems” (1896),<ref>Böhm-Bawerk, Eugen Ritter von; “Zum Abschluss des Marxschen Systems” <nowiki>[</nowiki>“On the Closure of the Marxist System”<nowiki>]</nowiki>, ''Staatswiss. Arbeiten. Festgabe für [[Karl Knies|K. Knies]]'' (1896).</ref> but the first was Wicksteed's “The Marxian Theory of Value. ''Das Kapital'': a criticism” (1884,<ref>Wicksteed, Philip Henry; “Das Kapital: A Criticism”, ''To-day'' 2 (1884) pp. 388–409.</ref> followed by “The Jevonian criticism of Marx: a rejoinder” in 1885<ref>Wicksteed, Philip Henry; “The Jevonian criticism of Marx: a rejoinder”, ''To-day'' 3 (1885) pp. 177–9.</ref>). The most famous early Marxist responses were [[Rudolf Hilferding]]'s ''Böhm-Bawerks Marx-Kritik'' (1904)<ref name="hilferding">Hilferding, Rudolf; ''Böhm-Bawerks Marx-Kritik'' (1904). Translated as ''Böhm-Bawerk's Criticism of Marx''.</ref> and ''The Economic Theory of the Leisure Class'' (1914) by [[Nikolai Bukharin]].<ref name="bukharin">[[Nikolai Bukharin]]; ''Политической экономии рантье'' (1914). Translated as [http://www.marxists.org/archive/bukharin/works/1927/leisure-economics/ ''The Economic Theory of the Leisure Class''].</ref>
| |
| | |
| === Eclipse ===
| |
| In his 1881 work [http://socserv.mcmaster.ca/econ/ugcm/3ll3/edgeworth/mathpsychics.pdf ''Mathematical Psychics''], [[Francis Ysidro Edgeworth]] presented the [[indifference curve]], deriving its properties from marginalist theory which assumed utility to be a differentiable function of quantified goods and services. But it came to be seen that indifference curves could be considered as somehow ''given'', without bothering with notions of utility.
| |
| | |
| In 1915, [[Eugen Slutsky]] derived a theory of consumer choice solely from properties of indifference curves.<ref>[[Eugen Slutsky]]; “Sulla teoria del bilancio del consumatore”, ''Giornale degli Economisti'' 51 (1915).</ref> Because of [[World War I|the World War]], the [[October Revolution|Bolshevik Revolution]], and his own subsequent loss of interest, Slutsky's work drew almost no notice, but similar work in 1934 by [[John Hicks]] and [[R. G. D. Allen]]<ref>Hicks, John Richard, and Roy George Douglas Allen; “A Reconsideration of the Theory of Value”, ''Economica'' 54 (1934).</ref> derived much the same results and found a significant audience. (Allen subsequently drew attention to Slutksy's earlier accomplishment.)
| |
| | |
| Although some of the third generation of Austrian School economists had by 1911 rejected the quantification of utility while continuing to think in terms of marginal utility,<ref>[[von Mises, Ludwig Heinrich]]; ''[[Theorie des Geldes und der Umlaufsmittel]]'' (1912).</ref> most economists presumed that utility must be a sort of quantity. Indifference curve analysis seemed to represent a way of dispensing with presumptions of quantification, albeït that a seemingly arbitrary assumption (admitted by Hicks to be a “rabbit out of a hat”<ref>Hicks, Sir John Richard; ''Value and Capital'', Chapter I. “Utility and Preference” §8, p23 in the 2nd edition.</ref>) about decreasing marginal rates of substitution<ref name="hicks_vc">Hicks, Sir John Richard; ''Value and Capital'', Chapter I. “Utility and Preference” §7-8.</ref> would then have to be introduced to have convexity of indifference curves.
| |
| | |
| For those who accepted that superseded marginal utility analysis had been superseded by indifference curve analysis, the former became at best somewhat analogous to the [[Bohr model|Bohr model of the atom]] — perhaps pedagogically useful, but “old fashioned” and ultimately incorrect.<ref name="hicks_vc" /><ref name="samuelson">Samuelson, Paul Anthony; “Complementarity: An Essay on the 40th Anniversary of the Hicks-Allen Revolution in Demand Theory”, ''Journal of Economic Literature'' vol 12 (1974).</ref>
| |
| | |
| === Revival ===
| |
| When Cramer and Bernoulli introduced the notion of diminishing marginal utility, it had been to address [[St. Petersburg paradox|a paradox of gambling]], rather than the [[paradox of value]]. The marginalists of the revolution, however, had been formally concerned with problems in which there was neither [[risk]] nor [[uncertainty]]. So too with the indifference curve analysis of Slutsky, Hicks, and Allen.
| |
| | |
| The [[expected utility hypothesis]] of Bernoulli ''et alii'' was revived by various 20th century thinkers, perhaps most notably [[Frank P. Ramsey|Ramsey]] (1926),<ref>Ramsey, Frank Plumpton; “Truth and Probability” ([http://cepa.newschool.edu/het//texts/ramsey/ramsess.pdf PDF]), Chapter VII in ''The Foundations of Mathematics and other Logical Essays'' (1931).</ref> [[John von Neumann|v. Neumann]] and [[Oskar Morgenstern|Morgenstern]] (1944),<ref>von Neumann, John and Oskar Morgenstern; ''[[Theory of Games and Economic Behavior]]'' (1944).</ref> and [[Leonard Jimmie Savage|Savage]] (1954).<ref>Savage, Leonard Jimmie; ''Foundations of Statistics'' (1954).</ref> Although this hypothesis remains controversial, it brings not merely utility but a quantified conception thereof back into the mainstream of economic thought, and would dispatch the [[Occam's razor|Ockhamistic argument]].<ref name="samuelson" /> (It should perhaps be noted that, in expected utility analysis, the “law” of diminishing marginal utility corresponds to what is called “[[risk aversion]]”.)
| |
| | |
| == Criticisms==<!-- This section is linked from [[Economics]] -->
| |
| | |
| === Marxist attacks on marginalism ===
| |
| {{main|Marxism}}
| |
| [[Karl Marx]] died before marginalism became the interpretation of economic value accepted by mainstream economics. His theory was based on the [[labor theory of value]], which distinguishes between [[exchange value]] and [[use value]]. In his ''Capital'' he rejected the explanation of long-term market values by supply and demand:
| |
| :Nothing is easier than to realize the inconsistencies of demand and supply, and the resulting deviation of market-prices from market-values. The real difficulty consists in determining what is meant by the equation of supply and demand.
| |
| :[...]
| |
| :If supply equals demand, they cease to act, and for this very reason commodities are sold at their market-values. Whenever two forces operate equally in opposite directions, they balance one another, exert no outside influence, and any phenomena taking place in these circumstances must be explained by causes other than the effect of these two forces. If supply and demand balance one another, they cease to explain anything, do not affect market-values, and therefore leave us so much more in the dark about the reasons why the market-value is expressed in just this sum of money and no other.<ref>Marx, Karl; [http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1894-c3/ch10.htm ''Capital'' v. III pt. II ch. 10].</ref>
| |
| | |
| In his early response to marginalism, [[Nikolai Bukharin]] argued that "the subjective evaluation from which price is to be derived really starts from this price",<ref>Nikolai Bukharin (1914) ''The Economic Theory of the Leisure Class'', Chapter 3, Section 2.[http://www.marxists.org/archive/bukharin/works/1927/leisure-economics/ch03.htm#s6].</ref> concluding:
| |
| | |
| :Whenever the Böhm-Bawerk theory, it appears, resorts to individual motives as a basis for the derivation of social phenomena, he is actually smuggling in the social content in a more or less disguised form in advance, so that the entire construction becomes a vicious circle, a continuous logical fallacy, a fallacy that can serve only specious ends, and demonstrating in reality nothing more than the complete barrenness of modern bourgeois theory.<ref>Nicholai Bukharin (1914) ''The Economic Theory of the Leisure Class'', Chapter 3, Section 6.[http://www.marxists.org/archive/bukharin/works/1927/leisure-economics/ch03.htm#s6].</ref>
| |
| | |
| Similarly a later Marxist critic, [[Ernest Mandel]], argued that marginalism was "divorced from reality", ignored the role of production, and that:
| |
| :It is, moreover, unable to explain how, from the clash of millions of different individual "needs" there emerge not only uniform prices, but prices which remain stable over long periods, even under perfect conditions of free competition. Rather than an explanation of constants, and of the basic evolution of economic life, the "marginal" technique provides at best an explanation of ephemeral, short-term variations.<ref>Mandel, Ernest; ''Marxist Economic Theory'' (1962), [http://www.marxists.org/archive/mandel/works/marxist-economic-theory/marginalists.htm “The marginalist theory of value and neo-classical political economy”].</ref>
| |
| | |
| [[Maurice Dobb]] argued that prices derived through marginalism depend on the distribution of income. The ability of consumers to express their preferences is dependent on their spending power. As the theory asserts that prices arise in the act of exchange, Dobb argues that it cannot explain how the distribution of income affects prices and consequently cannot explain prices.<ref name="dobb">Dobb, Maurice; ''Theories of value and Distribution'' (1973).</ref>
| |
| | |
| Dobb also criticized the ''motives'' behind marginal utility theory. Jevons wrote, for example, "so far as is consistent with the inequality of wealth in every community, all commodities are distributed by exchange so as to produce the maximum social benefit." (See [[Fundamental theorems of welfare economics]].) Dobb contended that this statement indicated that marginalism is intended to insulate market economics from criticism by making prices the natural result of the given income distribution.<ref name="dobb" />
| |
| | |
| === Marxist adaptations to marginalism ===
| |
| Some economists strongly influenced by the [[Marxian]] tradition such as [[Oskar Lange]], [[Włodzimierz Brus]], and [[Michal Kalecki]] have attempted to integrate the insights of classical [[political economy]], marginalism, and [[neoclassical economics]]. They believed that Marx lacked a sophisticated theory of prices, and neoclassical economics lacked a theory of the social frameworks of economic activity. Some other Marxists have also argued that on one level there is no conflict between marginalism and Marxism: one could employ a marginalist theory of supply and demand within the context of a “big picture” understanding of the Marxist notion that capitalists exploit labor.<ref>Steedman, Ian; ''Socialism & Marginalism in Economics, 1870–1930'' (1995).</ref>
| |
| | |
| ===Structural critiques===
| |
| Social theorist [[Roberto Mangabeira Unger]]’s critique of Marginalism begins with [[Léon Walras|Walras’]] equilibrium theory, which attempted to achieve a certainty of economic analysis by putting aside normative controversies of social organization. Unger finds three weaknesses that crippled the theory: foremost, the theory claimed that equilibrium would be spontaneously generated in a market economy. In reality, a self-adjusting equilibrium fails to occur. Second, the theory puts forth a determinate image of the market. Historically, however, the market has been shown to be indeterminate with different market arrangements. Third, the polemical use of efficiency fails to account for the differences of distribution among individuals, classes, and generations.<ref name="Unger, Roberto Mangabeira 1987. pp. 123–125">Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 1987. Social Theory: Its Situation and Its Task. New York: Verso, pp. 123–125.</ref>
| |
| | |
| The consequences of the marginalist movement were profound for the study of economics, according to Unger. The most immediate problem is that under this generalizing tendency of economics, there is no means by which to incorporate empirical evidence and thus to reimagine the world and develop new theories and new directions. In this way, the discipline is always self-referential and theoretical. Furthermore, the lack of a normative view of the world curtails the ability to propose anything more than a policy prescription, which by definition always assumes a given context. The discipline can only rationalize the world and support a status quo. Lastly, Unger finds that this turn in economics ended up universalizing debates in macroeconomics and leaving the discipline without any historical perspective. A consequence, for example, was that Keynes’ solution to a particular historical crisis was turned into a general theory when it should only be understood as a response to a particular situation.<ref>Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 1987. Social Theory: Its Situation and Its Task. New York: Verso, pp. 127–128.</ref>
| |
| | |
| == References ==
| |
| {{reflist|2}}
| |
| | |
| == External links ==
| |
| * Backhouse, Roger E. "marginal revolution." The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. Second Edition. Eds. Steven N. Durlauf and Lawrence E. Blume. Palgrave Macmillan, 2008. The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics Online. Palgrave Macmillan. 16 May 2013 http://www.dictionaryofeconomics.com/article?id=pde2008_M000392 doi:10.1057/9780230226203.1026
| |
| * {{cite encyclopedia |last1=Rhoads |first1=Steven E. |authorlink1= |last2= |first2= |authorlink2= |editor= [[David R. Henderson]] (ed.) |encyclopedia=[[Concise Encyclopedia of Economics]] |title=Marginalism |url=http://www.econlib.org/library/Enc/Marginalism.html |year=2008 |edition= 2nd |publisher=[[Library of Economics and Liberty]] |location=Indianapolis |isbn=978-0865976658 |oclc=237794267}}
| |
| * McAfee, R. Preston; [http://www.introecon.com ''Introduction to Economic Analysis''].
| |
| | |
| {{Use dmy dates|date=January 2011}}
| |
| | |
| [[Category:History of economic thought]]
| |
| [[Category:Economic theories]]
| |
| [[Category:Value theory]]
| |
| [[Category:Marginal concepts]]
| |
| [[ar:نظرية حدية]]
| |