Great-circle distance: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>Ac44ck
Undid revision 505855646 by 72.44.101.238 (talk)r=1 for unit sphere
 
en>Cffk
→‎Computational Formulas: give reason for atan2
Line 1: Line 1:
{{about|the logical concept|the linguistic concept|double negative|the rule of inference of propositional logic based on the same concept|double negative elimination}}
{{Merge from|Double negative elimination|date=March 2012}}
In [[propositional calculus|propositional logic]], '''double negation''' is the [[theorem]] that states that "If a statement is true, then it is not the case that the statement is not true." This is expressed by saying that a proposition ''A'' is [[logical equivalence|logically equivalent]] to ''not (not-A''), or by the formula A ≡ ~(~A) where the sign ≡ expresses logical equivalence and the sign ~ expresses [[negation]].<ref>Or alternate symbolism such as A ↔ ¬(¬A) or Kleene's *49<sup>o</sup>: A ∾ ¬¬A (Kleene 1952:119; in the original Kleene uses an elongated tilde ∾ for logical equivalence, approximaed here with a "lazy S".)</ref>


Like the [[law of the excluded middle]], this principle is considered to be a [[law of thought]] in [[classical logic]],<ref>Hamilton is discussing [[Hegel]] in the following: "In the more recent systems of philosophy, the universality and necessity of the axiom of Reason has, with other logical laws, been controverted and rejected by speculators on the absolute.[''On principle of Double Negation as another law of Thought'', see Fries, ''Logik'', §41, p. 190; Calker, ''Denkiehre odor Logic und Dialecktik'', §165, p. 453; Beneke, ''Lehrbuch der Logic'', §64, p. 41.]" (Hamilton 1860:68)</ref> but it is disallowed by [[intuitionistic logic]].<ref>The <sup>o</sup> of Kleene's formula *49<sup>o</sup> indicates "the demonstration is not valid for both systems [classical system and intuitionistic system]", Kleene 1952:101.</ref>  The principle was stated as a theorem of [[propositional calculus|propositional logic]] by [[Bertrand Russell|Russell]] and [[Alfred Whitehead|Whitehead]] in  ''[[Principia Mathematica]]'' as:


Hi. The author's name is Eusebio remember, though , he never really liked that name. In his professional life he is literally a people manager. He's always loved living in Guam and he features everything that he has to have there. To drive is one of those things he loves the vast majority. He's been working about his website for various time now. Check that will out here: http://prometeu.net<br><br>my blog :: how to [http://Imageshack.us/photos/hack+clash hack clash] of clans ([http://prometeu.net click the up coming internet site])
:: <math>\mathbf{*4\cdot13}. \ \ \vdash.\ p \ \equiv \ \thicksim(\thicksim p)</math><ref>PM 1952 reprint of 2nd edition 1927 pages 101-102, page 117.</ref>
::"This is the principle of double negation, ''i.e.'' a proposition is equivalent of the falsehood of its negation."
 
The ''principium contradictiones'' of modern logicians (particularly Leibnitz and Kant) in the formula ''A'' is not not-''A'', differs entirely in meaning and application from the Aristotelian proposition [ i.e. [[Law of Contradiction]]: not (''A'' and not-''A'') i.e. ~(''A'' & ~''A''), or not (( ''B'' is ''A'') and (''B'' is not-''A''))]. This latter refers to the relation between an affirmative and a negative judgment. According to Aristotle, one judgment [''B'' is judged to be an ''A''] contradicts another [''B'' is judged to be a not-''A'']. The later proposition [ ''A'' is not not-''A'' ] refers to the relation between subject and predicate in a single judgment; the predicate contradicts the subject. Aristotle states that one judgment is false when another is true; the later writers [Leibniz and Kant] state that a judgment is in itself and absolutely false, because the predicate contradicts the subject. What the later writers desire is a principle from which it can be known whether certain propositions are in themselves true. From the Aristotelian proposition we cannot immediately infer the truth or falsehood of any particular proposition, but only the impossibility of believing both affirmation and negation at the same time.<ref>Sigwart ''1895:142-143</ref>
 
==Footnotes==
{{reflist}}
 
==References==
*[[Sir William Hamilton, 9th Baronet|William Hamilton]], 1860, ''Lectures on Metaphysics and Logic, Vol. II. Logic; Edited by Henry Mansel and John Veitch'', Boston, Gould and Lincoln. Available online from googlebooks.
*[[Christoph Sigwart]], 1895, ''Logic: The Judgment, Concept, and Inference; Second Edition, Translated by Helen Dendy'', Macmillan & Co. New York. Available online from googlebooks.
*[[Stephen C. Kleene]], 1952, ''Introduction to Metamathematics'', 6th reprinting with corrections 1971,  North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam NY, ISBN 0 7204 2103 9.
*[[Stephen C. Kleene]], 1967, ''Mathematical Logic'', Dover edition 2002, Dover Publicastions, Inc, Mineola N.Y. ISBN 0-486-42533-9 (pbk.)
*[[Alfred North Whitehead]] and [[Bertrand Russell]], ''Principia Mathematica to *56'', 2nd edition 1927, reprint 1962, Cambridge at the University Press, London UK, no ISBN or LCCCN.
 
[[Category:Theorems in propositional logic]]
[[Category:Classical logic]]

Revision as of 01:15, 25 January 2014

29 yr old Orthopaedic Surgeon Grippo from Saint-Paul, spends time with interests including model railways, top property developers in singapore developers in singapore and dolls. Finished a cruise ship experience that included passing by Runic Stones and Church. Library Technician Anton from Strathroy, has many passions that include r/c helicopters, property developers in condo new launch singapore and coin collecting. Finds the beauty in planing a trip to spots around the globe, recently only returning from Old Town of Corfu. In propositional logic, double negation is the theorem that states that "If a statement is true, then it is not the case that the statement is not true." This is expressed by saying that a proposition A is logically equivalent to not (not-A), or by the formula A ≡ ~(~A) where the sign ≡ expresses logical equivalence and the sign ~ expresses negation.[1]

Like the law of the excluded middle, this principle is considered to be a law of thought in classical logic,[2] but it is disallowed by intuitionistic logic.[3] The principle was stated as a theorem of propositional logic by Russell and Whitehead in Principia Mathematica as:

[4]
"This is the principle of double negation, i.e. a proposition is equivalent of the falsehood of its negation."

The principium contradictiones of modern logicians (particularly Leibnitz and Kant) in the formula A is not not-A, differs entirely in meaning and application from the Aristotelian proposition [ i.e. Law of Contradiction: not (A and not-A) i.e. ~(A & ~A), or not (( B is A) and (B is not-A))]. This latter refers to the relation between an affirmative and a negative judgment. According to Aristotle, one judgment [B is judged to be an A] contradicts another [B is judged to be a not-A]. The later proposition [ A is not not-A ] refers to the relation between subject and predicate in a single judgment; the predicate contradicts the subject. Aristotle states that one judgment is false when another is true; the later writers [Leibniz and Kant] state that a judgment is in itself and absolutely false, because the predicate contradicts the subject. What the later writers desire is a principle from which it can be known whether certain propositions are in themselves true. From the Aristotelian proposition we cannot immediately infer the truth or falsehood of any particular proposition, but only the impossibility of believing both affirmation and negation at the same time.[5]

Footnotes

43 year old Petroleum Engineer Harry from Deep River, usually spends time with hobbies and interests like renting movies, property developers in singapore new condominium and vehicle racing. Constantly enjoys going to destinations like Camino Real de Tierra Adentro.

References

  • William Hamilton, 1860, Lectures on Metaphysics and Logic, Vol. II. Logic; Edited by Henry Mansel and John Veitch, Boston, Gould and Lincoln. Available online from googlebooks.
  • Christoph Sigwart, 1895, Logic: The Judgment, Concept, and Inference; Second Edition, Translated by Helen Dendy, Macmillan & Co. New York. Available online from googlebooks.
  • Stephen C. Kleene, 1952, Introduction to Metamathematics, 6th reprinting with corrections 1971, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam NY, ISBN 0 7204 2103 9.
  • Stephen C. Kleene, 1967, Mathematical Logic, Dover edition 2002, Dover Publicastions, Inc, Mineola N.Y. ISBN 0-486-42533-9 (pbk.)
  • Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell, Principia Mathematica to *56, 2nd edition 1927, reprint 1962, Cambridge at the University Press, London UK, no ISBN or LCCCN.
  1. Or alternate symbolism such as A ↔ ¬(¬A) or Kleene's *49o: A ∾ ¬¬A (Kleene 1952:119; in the original Kleene uses an elongated tilde ∾ for logical equivalence, approximaed here with a "lazy S".)
  2. Hamilton is discussing Hegel in the following: "In the more recent systems of philosophy, the universality and necessity of the axiom of Reason has, with other logical laws, been controverted and rejected by speculators on the absolute.[On principle of Double Negation as another law of Thought, see Fries, Logik, §41, p. 190; Calker, Denkiehre odor Logic und Dialecktik, §165, p. 453; Beneke, Lehrbuch der Logic, §64, p. 41.]" (Hamilton 1860:68)
  3. The o of Kleene's formula *49o indicates "the demonstration is not valid for both systems [classical system and intuitionistic system]", Kleene 1952:101.
  4. PM 1952 reprint of 2nd edition 1927 pages 101-102, page 117.
  5. Sigwart 1895:142-143